Benjamin Gregg
Associate Professor — Ph.D., Ph.D., Politics, Princeton University; Ph.D., Philosophy, Freie Universität Berlin

Contact
- E-mail: bgregg@austin.utexas.edu
- Phone: 512-232-7274
- Office: MEZ 3.138
- Office Hours: Fall 20: Tuesday/Thursday 8-9:30am (virtual)
- Campus Mail Code: A1800
Interests
Social and political theory; bioethics of human genetic engineering; politics of artificial intelligence; human rights
Biography
Benjamin Gregg
B.A., Yale University; Ph.D., Princeton University; D. Phil., Freie Universität Berlin
https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9510-6147
Teaches political and social theory, and bioethics, informed by political science and sociology, at the University of Texas at Austin but also in Germany (Frankfurt/Oder), Japan (Tokyo Gaidai, Hokkaido), China (Beiwai, Tsinghua), Austria (Linz, Innsbruck) and Brazil (Goiãnia)
Studied with Michael Walzer in Princeton, Axel Honneth in Berlin, and Seyla Benhabib at Yale
PUBLICATIONS
BOOKS
- Gregg, B. forthcoming 2021. Creating Human Nature: The Political Challenges of Genetic Enhancement. New York: Cambridge University Press.
- Gregg, B. 2016. The Human Rights State: Justice Within and Beyond Sovereign Nations. University of Pennsylvania Press. Philadelphia.
Focus of special issue (2017) International Journal of Human Rights, 21(3), “A Realistic Utopia: Critical Analyses of The Human Rights State”
Subject of international symposium (2016), Faculty of Law, Lund University, Sweden, April
- Gregg, B. 2012. Human Rights as Social Construction. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge, UK.
In Press. Chinese translation by Xianfei Lee. Cambridge University Press and Renmin University Press. Cambridge, UK and Beijing, China. Publication expected February 2021.
Among Cambridge University Press’ top ten bestsellers in political theory, Fall 2012 Interviewed on PBS station KLRU about book, August 2012
On the syllabus of the honors bachelor’s degree curriculum in Politics, Psychology and Sociology Tripos (PPS) at Cambridge University
First hardcover printing sold out seven months after publication; second printing, sold out August 2012; two additional printings of hardcover; paperback edition published 2013
- Gregg, B. 2003. Thick Moralities, Thin Politics: Social Integration across Communities of Belief. Duke University Press. Durham.
Focus of special issue (2012) Comparative Sociology, 11(5), “Comparative Perspectives on Social Integration in Pluralistic Societies: Thick Norms versus Thin”
- Gregg, B. 2003. Coping in Politics with Indeterminate Norms: A Theory of Enlightened Localism. SUNY Press. Albany.
Focus of special issue (2010) Comparative Sociology, 9(5), “Enlightened Localism in Comparative Perspective”
PEER-REVIEWED JOURNAL ARTICLES AND BOOK CHAPTERS
- Gregg, B. forthcoming, 2021. Political Bioethics. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy.
- Gregg, B. forthcoming, 2021. Against Essentialism in Conceptions of Human Rights and Human Nature. Human Rights Quarterly.
- Gregg, B. forthcoming, 2021. Human Rights Require yet Contest National Sovereignty. In A. Santos Campos and S. Cadilha, eds. Sovereignty as Value. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.
- Gregg, B. 2020. Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Biotechnik: Zur normativen Einschätzung der Humangenmanipulation [On the Use and Abuse of Biotechnology: Toward a Normative Evaluation of Human Genetic Engineering]. In B. Keplinger, F. Schwanniger, eds. Optimierung des Menschen [The Genetic Optimization of the Human Being]. Innsbruck, Austria: Studienverlag:49-63.
- Gregg, B. 2020. Beyond Due Diligence: The Human Rights Corporation. Human Rights Review. 25 pages. On-line at https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-020-00605-x, print to follow.
- Gregg, B. 2020. The Human Rights State: Advancing Justice through Political Imagination. In K. Schmidt, ed. The State of Human Rights: Historical Genealogies, Political Controversies, and Cultural Imaginaries:47-69. Heidelberg, Germany: Winter Verlag.
- Gregg, B. 2020. Construção Social de uma Natureza Humana Voltada para os Direitos Humanos [Social Construction of a Human Rights-Oriented Human Nature]. Boletim Goiano de Geografia [Brazil] 40:1-24.
- Gregg, B. 2020. The Indigenous Rights State. Ratio Juris 33(1):98-116.
- Gregg, B. 2019. Against Self-Isolation as a Human Right of Indigenous Peoples in Latin America. Human Rights Review 20(3):313-333.
- Gregg, B. 2019. Indigeneity as Social Construct and Political Tool. Human Rights Quarterly 41(4):823–848.
- Gregg, B. 2018. How to read for current developments in human genetics relevant to justice. Politics and the Life Sciences 37(2):262-277.
- Gregg, B. 2018. The Coming Political Challenges of Artificial Intelligence. Digital Culture & Society 4(1):157-180.
- Gregg, B. 2018. Human Genetic Engineering: Biotic Justice in the Anthropocene? In D. DellaSala and M. Goldstein, eds. Encyclopedia of the Anthropocene, vol. 4:351-359. Oxford, UK: Elsevier.
- Gregg, B. 2017. The human rights state: theoretical challenges, empirical deployments: reply to my critics. The International Journal of Human Rights 21(3):359-385.
- Wolfsteller, René and Gregg, B. 2017. A realistic utopia? Critical analyses of The Human Rights State in theory and deployment: Guest editors’ introduction. The International Journal of Human Rights 21(3):219-229.
- Gregg, B. 2016. A Socially Constructed Human Right to the Self-Determination of Indigenous Peoples [Un constructo social de los Derechos Humanos para la autodeterminación de los pueblos indígenas]. Deusto Journal of Human Rights 1 [Spain]:105-143.
- Gregg, B. 2016. Human Rights as Metaphor for Political Community Beyond the Nation State. Critical Sociology 42(6):897-917.
- Gregg, B. 2015. Advancing Human Rights in Post-Authoritarian Communities through Education. Journal of Human Rights Practice 7(2):199-222.
- Koppelman, A. and Gregg, B. 2014. Critical Exchange on Human Rights as Social Construction. Contemporary Political Theory 13(4):380-386.
- Gregg, B. 2014. Teaching Human Rights in the College Classroom as a Cognitive Style. In J. Shefner, H. Dahms, R. Jones, and A. Jalata, eds. Social Justice and the University. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave:253-279.
- Gregg, B. 2013. Might the Noble Savage have Joined the Earliest Cults of Rousseau? In J. Reiling and D. Tröhler, eds. Entre hétérogénéité et imagination. Pratiques de la réception de Jean-Jacques Rousseau [Between Heterogeneity and Imagination: Interpretive Approaches to Jean-Jacques Rousseau]. Genève, Switzerland: Éditions Slatkine:347-366.
- Gregg, B. 2012. Comparative Perspectives on Social Integration in Pluralistic Societies: Thick Norms versus Thin. Comparative Sociology 11(5):629-648.
- Gregg, B. 2012. Politics Disembodied and Deterritorialized: The Internet as Human Rights Resource. In H. Dahms and L. Hazelrigg, eds. Theorizing Modern Society as a Dynamic Process. Bingley, UK: Emerald:209-233.
- Gregg, B. 2012. Genetic Enhancement: A New Dialectic of Enlightenment? In D. Wetzel, ed. Perspektiven der Aufklärung: Zwischen Mythos und Realität [Perspectives on the Enlightenment: Between Myth and Reality]. Paderborn, Germany: Verlag Wilhelm Fink:133-146.
- Gregg, B. 2010. Individuals as Authors of Human Rights: Not only Addressees. Theory and Society 39(6):631-650.
- Gregg, B. 2010. Deploying Cognitive Sociology to Advance Human Rights. Comparative Sociology 9(3):279-307.
- Gregg, B. 2010. Anti-Imperialism: Generating Universal Human Rights Out of Local Norms. Ratio Juris 23(3):289-310.
- Gregg, B. 2010. Enlightened Localism in Comparative Perspective. Comparative Sociology 9(5):563-593.
- Gregg, B. 2009. Familiendämmerung in Amerika? [Twilight of the American Family?]. In S. Caspar und C. Gehrke, eds. Familien-Bande [Families as Idiosyncrasies]. Tübingen, Germany: Konkursbuch Verlag:321-329.
- Gregg, B. 2008. Translating Human Rights into Muslim Vernaculars. Comparative Sociology 7(4):457–483.
- Gregg, B. 2002. Proceduralism Reconceived: Political Conflict Resolution under Conditions of Moral Pluralism. Theory and Society 31(6):741-776.
- Gregg, B. 2002. The Law and Courts of Enlightened Localism. Polity 35(2):283-309.
- Gregg, B. 1999. Using Legal Rules in an Indeterminate World: Overcoming the Limitations of Jurisprudence. Political Theory 27(3):389-410.
According to its website, at one point among the top 10 of the 50 most frequently-cited articles published in Political Theory
- Gregg, B. 1999. Adjudicating Among Competing Systems of Belief. International Review of Sociology 9(1):7-17.
- Gregg, B. 1998. Jurisprudence in an Indeterminate World: Pragmatist not Postmodern. Ratio Juris 11(4):382-398.
- Gregg, B. 1995. Law in China: The Tug of Tradition, the Push of Capitalism. Review of Central and East European Law 21(1):65-86.
- Gregg, B. 1994. Possibility of Social Critique in an Indeterminate World. Theory and Society 23(3):327-366.
Japanese translation in Hokkudai Hogaku Ronshu [Hokkaido Law Journal]. 1999. 50(3):235-256 and 50(4):335-365.
- Gregg, B. 1994. Regulating Commercial Speech: A Question Political Not Legal. State Constitutional Commentaries and Notes 5(3):18-29.
- Gregg, B. 1994. Puragumattiku na hogaku no kanosei [Possibility of a Pragmatic Jurisprudence (Japan)]. Chiba Journal of Law and Politics 8(3):97-119 [Part I] and 8(4):59-109 [Part II].
- Gregg, B. 1993. The Modernization of Contemporary Chinese Law. The Review of Politics 55(3):443-470.
- Gregg. B. 1993. The Fate of Liberalism in the New, Tripolar World-Order. In Y. Ogasawara, ed. Chiiki-Funso to Sogoizon [Regional Conflict and Interdependence]. Tokyo: University of Foreign Studies Press:1-27.
- Gregg, B. 1992. The Parameters of Possible Constitutional Interpretation. In R. Wuthnow, ed. Vocabularies of Public Life: Empirical Essays in Symbolic Structure. London: Routledge:207-233.
Japanese translation in Kokugakuin Hogaku [Kokugakuin Journal of Law and Politics, (Tokyo)]. 1995. 32(2) [Part I] and 32(3) [Part II].
- Gregg, B. 1988. Falankefu xuepai dui lixin tongzhi de pipan [Frankfurt School’s Critique of Rational Authority]. Guowai Shehui Xue [International Sociology (Beijing)] 4:3-9.
JOURNAL ARTICLES CURRENTLY UNDER PEER REVIEW
- Gregg, B. Submitted. Deploying Epigenetics to Identify Biologically Influenced Social Inequalities.
- Gregg, B. Submitted. Human Dignity as Social Construct and Political Tool for Regulating Human Genetic Engineering.
- Gregg, B. Submitted. A Human Right to Freedom From Genetic Disability.
- Gregg, B. Submitted. Containing COVID-19: When an Individual Human Right to Privacy Confronts a Collective Human Right to Health.
- Gregg, B. Submitted. Less-than-Universal Standards for the Legal Regulation of Human Genetic Engineering
- Gregg, B. and Heitor Pagliaro. In Preparation. Authoritarian Democracy in Brazil Today.
WORKS IN PROGRESS
- Gregg, B. In Preparation: Book titled Indigeneity as Social Construct and Political Tool: Human Rights in the Self-Determination of Endangered Communities (Berlin: DeGruyter).
- Gregg, B. In Preparation: Review of Auch eine Geschichte der Philosophie by Jürgen Habermas (Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp Verlag, 2018). Kritikon Litterarum. Forthcoming 2021.
- Gregg, B. In Preparation: Review of Becoming Human: A Theory of Ontogeny by Michael Tomasello (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2019). International Dialogue. Forthcoming 2021.
REVIEWS AND TRANSLATIONS
BOOK REVIEWS
- Gregg, B. 2020. Review of Not Enough: Human Rights in an Unequal World by Samuel Moyn (2018. Kritikon Litterarum [International Book Review for American, English, Romance, and Slavic Studies] 47 (3-4):376-381.
- Gregg, B. 2019. Review of Enhanced Beings: Human Germline Modification and the Law by Kerry Lynn Macintosh (2018. Choice: Current Reviews for Academic Libraries, 56(5). Choice Review #56-2123.
- Gregg, B. 2018. Review of The Moral Conflict of Law and Neuroscience by Peter Alces. 2018. Choice: Current Reviews for Academic Libraries, 55(11). Choice Review #55-4221.
- Gregg, B. 2018. Review of The Promise of Human Rights: Constitutional Government, Democratic Legitimacy, and International Law by Jamie Mayerfield (2016). Contemporary Political Theory 17(S1):S30-S34.
- Gregg, B. 2015. Review of Making Human: World Order and the Global Governance of Human Dignity by Matthew Weinert (2015). Human Right Quarterly 37:1101-1104.
- Gregg, B. 2013. Review of Philip Selznick: Ideals in the World by Martin Krygier (2012). Law and Politics Book Review 23:264-267.
- Gregg, B. 2013. Review of Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues, by James Fleming and Linda McClain (2013). Choice: Current Reviews for Academic Libraries 51(1). DOI: 10.5860/Choice.51-0538.
- Gregg, B. 2013. Review of The Ironic Spectator: Solidarity in the Age of Posthumanitarianism, by Lilie Chouliaraki (2013). Choice: Current Reviews for Academic Libraries 51(4). DOI: 10.5860/Choice.51-2343.
- Gregg, B. 2013. Review of Dialectics of Human Nature in Marx’s Philosophy, by Mehmet Tabak (2013). Choice: Current Reviews for Academic Libraries 50(11). DOI: 10.5860/Choice.50-6444.
- Gregg, B. 2012. Review of Human Rights and Memory, by Daniel Levy and Natan Sznaider (2010) and Review of Humanitarianism and Modern Culture, by Keith Tester (2010). Perspectives on Politics 10(2):456-458.
- Gregg, B. 2008. Review of In Defense of Human Rights: A Non-Religious Grounding in a Pluralistic World, by Ari Kohen (2007). Perspectives on Politics 6(2):373-374.
- Gregg, B. 2008. Review of Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth, and Happiness, by Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein (2008). Law and Politics Book Review 18(5):452-455.
- Gregg, B. 2007. Review of Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire, by Wendy Brown (2006). Law and Politics Book Review 17(4):318-325.
- Gregg, B. and Williams, D.L. 2006. Review of Rousseau and Law, by Thom Brooks, Ed. (2006). Law and Politics Book Review 16(5):372-383.
- Gregg, B. 2004. Review of Legality and Legitimacy, by Carl Schmitt, Translated and Edited by Jeffrey Seitzer (2004). Law and Politics Book Review 14(8):619-623.
- Gregg, B. 1998. Review of Between the Norm and the Exception: The Frankfurt School and the Rule of Law, by William Scheuerman (1994). Political Theory, 26(2):237-244.
- Gregg, B. 1997. Review of Between Facts and Norms, by Jürgen Habermas (1997). Review of Politics 59(4):927-930.
- Gregg, B. 1997. Review of China's Legal Awakening. Legal Theory and Criminal Justice in Deng’s Era, by Carlos Wing-hung Lo (1997). Review of Central and East European Law 23(2):165-172.
- Gregg, B. 1994. The Failed Quest for a Principled Jurisprudence. Review of Common Law and Liberal Theory, by James Stoner (1994). Legal Studies Forum 18(1):113-123.
- Gregg, B. 1989. Review of Kritik der Macht. Reflexionsstufen einer kritischen Gesellschaftstheorie [The Critique of Power. Reflective Stages in a Critical Social Theory], by Axel Honneth (1988). New German Critique 47:183-188.
- Gregg, B. 1989. Review of From Marx to Kant, by Dick Howard (1988). Theory and Society 18:417-423.
- Gregg, B. 1987. Modernity in Frankfurt: Must a History of Philosophy be a Philosophy of History? Review of Norm, Critique, and Utopia, by Seyla Benhabib (1986). Theory and Society 16:139-151.
- Gregg, B. 1987. In Defense of a Skeptical Rationalism. Reply to Benhabib’s reply to review of Norm, Critique, and Utopia, by Seyla Benhabib (1986). Theory and Society, 16:159-163.
- Gregg, B. 1984. Review of Theory and Politics by, Helmut Dubiel (1984). Telos, 61: 207-214.
TRANSLATIONS
- Gregg, B. 1998. Portions of Technology, War and Fascism, by Herbert Marcuse (Vol. 1 of the Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse). Douglas Kellner, ed. Routledge. New York, NY:231-260.
- Gregg. B. 1993. Can an Ultimate Foundation of Knowledge Be Non-Metaphysical? by Karl-Otto Apel. Journal of Speculative Philosophy 7:171-190.
- Gregg, B. 1988. “Felicitation,” by Jürgen Habermas. In An Unmastered Past, Martin Jay, ed. University of California Press. Berkeley:9-15.
- Gregg, B. 1988. “The Left in Germany Has Failed,” by Leo Lowenthal. In An Unmastered Past, Martin Jay, ed. University of California Press. Berkeley:247-261.
- Gregg, B. 1988. “Against Postmodernism,” by Leo Lowenthal. In An Unmastered Past, Martin Jay, ed. University of California Press. Berkeley:261-269.
- Gregg, B. 1987. “Introduction” to Daniel Paul Schreber. In Memoirs of My Nervous Illness, Ida Macallpine and Richard Hunter, trans. and eds. Harvard University Press. Cambridge:vii-liv.
- Gregg, B. 1987. “What is Neo-Aristotelianism?” by Herbert Schnädelbach. Praxis International 3-4:226-237.
- Gregg, B. 1986. “The Search for ‘Normality’ in the Relationship between Germans and Jews,” by Sigrid Meuschel. New German Critique 38:39-56.
- Gregg, B. 1985. Theory and Politics: Studies in the Development of Critical Theory, by Helmut Dubiel. MIT Press. Cambridge.
RECENT VISITING RESEARCH AND FELLOW POSITIONS
2021 Visiting Researcher, Centre for Biomedical Ethics, Yong Loo Lin School of Medicine, National University of Singapore
2019 Visiting Researcher, 2019 Visiting Researcher, Centre de Recherches Interdisciplinaires, Université Paris 5 René Descartes, Paris, France
2019 Visiting Researcher, Danish Institute for Human Rights, Copenhagen, Denmark
2018 Visiting Researcher, Centre for Sami Studies, University of Tromsø, Norway
2018 Visiting Fellow, Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics and the Ethox Centre, Nuffield Department of Population Health, University of Oxford, UK
2016 Visiting Researcher, Interdisciplinary Center for Bioethics, Yale University, New Haven, CT
2016 Visiting Researcher, The Hastings Center, Garrison, NY
INVITED PROFESSOR, INTERNATIONAL GRADUATE MASTER CLASSES
2019 Universidade Federal de Goiás [Federal University of Goiás], Programa de Pós- Graduação Interdisciplinar em Direito Humanos [Interdisciplinary Graduate Program in Human Rights]. Goiânia, Brazil.
2019 University of Halle, Research Cluster “Gesellschaft und Kultur in Bewegung” [Society and Culture in Motion]. Martin-Luther-Universität Halle-Wittenberg [Martin Luther University of Halle-Wittenberg]. Halle, Germany.
2016 University of Hokkaido, School of Law. Sapporo, Japan.
2015 University of Glasgow, Human Rights Network. Scotland, UK. University of Texas
SCHOLARLY PRESENTATIONS
INVITED TALKS
(Scheduled) “Political Bioethics.” Series of talks on political bioethics. Centre for Biomedical Ethics, Yong Loo Lin School of Medicine. National University of Singapore. Singapore. June-August 2021.
“Human Rights as a Politics of Imagination: Morality Beyond Tradition, Solidarity Without Nationalism, Justice Authored by Its Addressees,” Globalizing Education Faculty Learning Community (collaboration between Hemispheres Consortium at UT Austin and International Programs at Austin Community College), UT Austin. October 2020.
(Invited but Declined) “The Anthropocene and Global Inequality: The Task for Human Rights.” Raoul Wallenberg Institute for Human Rights and the Earth System Governance Project. University of Lund. Lund, Sweden. October 2019.
Keynote Address. “How to Oppose Authoritarian Democracy in Brazil: A Guide for Citizens.” X Seminário Pensar Direitos Humanos: Direitos Humanos em tempos neoliberais e antihumanistas [Thinking Human Rights: Human Rights in Neoliberal and Antihumanist Times]. Universidade Federal de Goiás [Federal University of Goiás]. Goiânia, Brazil. September 2019.
“Political Challenges of Regulating Human Genetic Engineering.” Centre de recherches interdisciplinaires [Center for Research and Interdisciplinarity]. Paris, France. July 2019.
“The Coming Political Challenges of Artificial Intelligence.” Information Technology University of Copenhagen. Copenhagen, Denmark. June 2019.
“Beyond Due Diligence: The Human Rights Corporation.” Danish Institute for Human Rights. Copenhagen, Denmark. June 2019.
“Political Bioethics: Deciding Difficult Bioethical Issues Under Conditions of Value Pluralism and Deep Disagreement.” Martin-Luther-Universität Halle-Wittenberg. [Martin Luther University of Halle-Wittenberg]. Halle, Germany. May 2019.
“The Coming Political Challenges of Artificial Intelligence.” Institut für Geschichte und Ethik der Medizin, Martin-Luther-Universität Halle-Wittenberg [Institute for History and Ethics of Medicine, Martin Luther University of Halle-Wittenberg]. Halle, Germany. May 2019.
“Deploying Epigenetics to Identify Genetically Influenced Social Inequalities.” Nuffield Department of Population Health, Ethox Centre, University of Oxford. Oxford, UK. December 2018.
“Political Bioethics.” St. Cross Lecture in Ethics, Department of Philosophy, University of Oxford. Oxford, UK. November 2018.
“Can Corporate Profit-Seeking Accord with Human Rights-Promotion?” Adam Smith School of Business, University of Glasgow. Glasgow, Scotland. September 2018.
“Human Rights Advocacy as Bottom-Up Politics that Deploys the Rule of Law, Democracy, Cosmopolitan Declarations and International Law.” Bayerische Amerika-Akademie, Stiftung Bayerisches Amerikahaus [Bavarian American Academy, Bavarian Center for Transatlantic Relations]. Munich, Germany. July 2018.
“Therapie und Enhancement der Human-Intelligenz: Was leisten die Menschenrechte?” [Genetic Therapy and Genetic Enhancement of Human Intelligence: What Regulatory Guidance Might Human Rights Provide?] Katholische Hochschule für Sozialwesen [Catholic University of Social Services]. Berlin, Germany. April 2018.
“Why the Difference Between Two Forms of Engineered Intelligence Matters: AI and Genetically Manipulated Humans.” School of Psychology, National University of Ireland. Galway, Ireland. February 2018.
“Can Biological Science Advance Social Justice?” School of Psychology, Psi Chi Honours Society, National University of Ireland. Galway, Ireland. February 2018.
“Social Theory at the Margins of the Social: Epigenetics, Artificial Intelligence, and the Anthropocene.” Department of Sociology, University of Tennessee. Knoxville, TN. October 2017.
“Social and Political Challenges of Human Genetic Engineering.” Department of Sociology, University of Tennessee. Knoxville, TN. October 2017.
“Self-Authored Human Rights.” IESB Centro Universitário [Higher Education Institute of Brasília]. Brasília, Brazil. August 2017.
“A Human Right Not to Democracy but to the Rule of Law.” IESB Centro Universitário [Higher Education Institute of Brasília]. Brasília, Brazil. August 2017.
“On The Human Rights State and Latin America.” Universidade de Brasília [University of Brasília]. Brasília, Brazil. August 2017.
“The Role of Organized Civil Society in Constructing a Human Rights State in Brazil.” OAB-DF [Order of Attorneys of Brazil-Distrito Federal (Brazilian Bar Association, Federal District)]. Brasília, Brazil. August 2017.
“Genetically Informed Personalized Education: Promises and Perils for Social Justice.” The Hastings Center. Garrison, NY. August 2016.
“A Human Rights Framework for Evaluating the Genetic Engineering of Intelligence.” The Hastings Center. Garrison, NY. July 2016.
“Human Rights as Social Construction: In Dialogue with the Jesuit Tradition.” Human Rights Institute, University of Deusto. Bilbao, Spain. June 2016.
“The Human Rights Challenges Posed by Human Genetic Engineering.” Norwegian Centre for Human Rights, University of Oslo. Oslo, Norway. June 2016.
“Die menschliche Natur als Technologieprodukt: Träume und Albträume der Genmanipulation” [Human Nature as a Product of Technology: Promises and Perils of Human Genetic Manipulation]. University of Linz. Linz, Austria. June 2016.
“The Human Rights Challenges of Human Genetic Engineering.” Erik Castrén Institute of International Law and Human Rights. Helsinki, Finland. May 2016.
“The Human Rights State: Political Community Beyond the Nation State.” Institute of Philosophy, Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic. Prague, Czech Republic. May 2016.
“Human Genetic Engineering: Pressing Issues of Law, Medicine, and Ethics.” DeCode Genetics (biopharmaceutical company known for its discoveries in human genetics). Reykjavík, Iceland. April 2016.
“Genetically Informed Personalized Education: Promises and Perils for Social Justice.” Higher Seminar in Practical Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Lund University. Lund, Sweden. April 2016.
“The Human Rights Challenge of Genetic Engineering.” Raul Wallenberg Institute, Lund University. Lund, Sweden. April 2016.
“The Relationship between Human Rights and Democracy.” Department of Political Science, University of Missouri. Columbia, MO. September 2015.
“Human Rights as Constructs: Without Religion or Metaphysics.” Centre for Contemporary Aristotelian Studies in Ethics and Politics, London Metropolitan University. London, UK. May 2015.
“Fundamental Questions for Political Community Posed by Genetic Manipulation.” University of the West of Scotland. Paisely, UK. May 2015.
Keynote Address. “Challenges to Human Rights Theory and Practice.” Glasgow Human Rights Network, University of Glasgow. Glasgow, Scotland. May 2015.
“Do Human Rights Require Democracy and the Rule of Law?” International Political Science Association World Congress, Montréal, Québec, July 2014.
Keynote Address. “Advancing Human Rights by Bringing Them Down to Earth.” Student World Assembly. Norwalk, CT. November 2014.
“The Pathology of the Surveillance State: On Reading My Stasi File.” British Studies Seminar, University of Texas at Austin. October 2013.
“Self-Granted Human Rights.” University of Nebraska. Lincoln, NE. January 2011.
“Aufgeklärte Eugenik oder Eugenik wider Gleichheit?” [Enlightened Eugenics or Eugenics Undermining Equality?] Société suisse de Sociologie [Swiss Sociological Association]. Bern, Switzerland. September 2010.
CONFERENCE PRESENTATIONS
PARTICIPATION IN ROUNDTABLES ON AUTHOR’S BOOKS
“Roundtable on B. Gregg’s, The Human Rights State.” Annual Meeting of the Southern Political Science Association. Austin, TX. January 2019.
“Roundtable on B.’s The Human Rights State.” Faculty of Law, Lund University, Sweden. April 2016
“Author-Meets-Critics Roundtable on B. Gregg’s, Human Rights as Social Construction.” Annual Meeting of the American Sociological Association. San Francisco, CA. August 2014.
CONFERENCE PAPERS
(Proposal under Review). “Social Science and Evolutionary Biology: Toward a Political Bioethics.” Symposium on the History, Philosophy and Sociology of School Biology. Dublin City University. Ireland. December. Virtual participation via Zoom.
(Proposal under Review). “Catholic Ecclesia, Authoritarian Governments, and Human Rights Advocates: Competition Among Self-Appointed Stewards of the Indigenous Peoples of the Amazon.” Faculty of Law and Administration, University of Warsaw. Poland. September 2020. Virtual participation via Zoom.
“Against Self-Isolation as a Human Right of Indigenous Peoples.” Annual Meeting of the Southern Political Science Association. San Juan, Puerto Rico. January 2020.
“Indigeneity as Social Construct and Political Tool.” Annual Meeting of the Southern Political Science Association. San Juan, Puerto Rico. January 2020.
“Against Self-Isolation as a Human Right of Indigenous Peoples.” Philosophy, Politics, Anthropology & Allied Disciplines Conference. University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam, The Netherlands. May 2019.
“Epigenetics as a Political Theory of Genetically Influenced Social Inequalities.” 24th World Congress of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Beijing University. Beijing, China. August 2018.
“Epigenetics as a Political Theory of Genetically Influenced Social Inequalities.” International Society for the History, Philosophy, and Social Study of Biology, Institute of Biosciences, University of São Paulo. São Paulo, Brazil. July 2017.
“Genetic Engineering of Human Intelligence: Moral, Legal, and Political Issues.” Humanities Research Award Symposium, University of Texas at Austin. March 2017.
“Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Biotechnik: Zur normativen Einschätzung der Humangenmanipulation” [“On the Use and Abuse of Biotechnology: The Normative Evaluation of Human Genetic Manipulation”]. Fifth Annual International Hartheim Conference on “Genetische Optimierung: Gentechnik und Fortpflanzungsmedizin” [Genetic Perfection: Gene Technology and Reproductive Medicine]. Alkoven, Austria. November 2016.
(Accepted but Declined.) “Genetic Justice: A Political Framework for Regulating Human Genetic Enhancement.” European Consortium for Political Research General Conference. Charles University. Prague, Czech Republic. September 2016.
“Fetus Ex Machina: The Political Challenge of Genetic Engineering.” Annual Meeting of the Association for Politics and the Life Sciences. University of Wisconsin. Madison, WI. October 2015.
“Social Inequalities in the Enhancement of Health through Genetic Manipulation.” European Consortium for Political Research General Conference, Standing Group on Political Theory. Université de Montréal [University of Montreal]. Montreal, Canada. August 2015.
“Genetic Diversity Among Humans: A Human Rights Issue?” International Society for the History, Philosophy, and Social Study of Biology. Université du Québec à Montréal [University of Quebec at Montreal]. Montreal, Canada. July 2015.
“A Human Right Not to Democracy but to the Rule of Law.” Annual Conference of the Association for Social and Political Philosophy, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam, The Netherlands. June 2015.
“The Body as Human Rights Boundary.” Annual Meeting of the American Sociological Association. San Francisco, CA. August 2014.
“Human Rights and ‘Humanitarian’ Military Intervention.” Critical Sociology Conference. San Francisco, CA. August 2014.
“The Local Construction of a Human Right to Democracy.” XVIII International Sociological Association World Congress. Yokohama, Japan. July 2014.
“What Cognitive Sociology Can Contribute to Human Rights Diffusion” XVIII International Sociological Association World Congress. Yokohama, Japan. July 2014.
“Human Rights Patriotism.” Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. Chicago, IL. September 2013.
(Accepted but Declined.) “Translating Human Rights into Local Muslim Vernaculars.” European Sociological Association Annual Conference. Università degli Studi di Torino [University of Turin]. Turin, Italy. August 2013.
“International Relations in a Community of Human Rights States.” American Sociological Association, Conference on Re-Imagining Human Rights. New York, NY. August 2013.
“Developing Human Rights Commitment in Post-Communist Societies through Education.” Russian Political Science Association and International Political Science Association Research Committee. St. Petersburg, Russia. June 2013.
“The Human Rights State: Nongeographic ‘Borders’ Embedded in the Citizen.” Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association. Chicago, IL. April 2013.
“Human Rights Patriotism.” Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. Chicago, IL. September 2013.
“International Relations in a Community of Human Rights States.” American Sociological Association. New York, NY. August 2013.
“The Human Rights State: Nongeographic ‘Borders’ Embedded in the Citizen.” Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association. Chicago, IL. April 2013.
“Abstracting from Human Bodies and National Boundaries via Electronically Mediated Communication: The Internet as Human Rights Resource.” Southern Sociological Society. New Orleans, LA. March 2012.
“Für die Bildung einer kritischen Internet-Öffentlichkeit gegen politische Alltagsentfremdung und–asymmetrie” [Against Alienation and Asymetry in Daily Life: Toward a Critical Public Sphere in the Internet]. Dritter gemeinsamer Kongress für Soziologie der Deutschen Gesellschaft für Soziologie, der Österreichischen Gesellschaft für Soziologie und der Schweizerischen Gesellschaft für Soziologie [Third Joint Congress for Sociology of the German Sociological Association, the Austrian Sociological Association, and the Swiss Sociological Association]. Innsbruck, Austria. October 2011.
“Menschenrechtsnormen als Subjekte des Strukturwandels der Weltöffentlichkeit: Auf dem Wege zu einem Pluralismus” [Human Rights Norms in the Structural Transformation of the Global Public Sphere: The Path to Human Rights Pluralism]. Dritter gemeinsamer Kongress für Soziologie der Deutschen Gesellschaft für Soziologie, der Österreichischen Gesellschaft für Soziologie und der Schweizerischen Geselleschaft für Soziologie [Third Joint Congress for Sociology of the German Sociological Association, the Austrian Sociological Association, and the Swiss Sociological Association]. Innsbruck, Austria. October 2011.
“The Genetic Self-Enhancement of the Human Species: Human Nature as Cultural Choice.” Political Studies Association. London, UK. April 2011.
“Rendering Human Rights Cosmopolitan Absent Universally Valid Norms.” Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. Washington, DC. September 2010.
“Community, Security and Universalism: Conflicting Priorities in Early Modern Thought on International Relations.” With graduate student Peter Mohanty. Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. Toronto, Canada. September 2009.
“Not only Addressees: Individuals as Authors of Human Rights.” Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association. Chicago, IL. April 2009.
“Deploying Cognitive Sociology to Advance Human Rights.” Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association. Chicago, IL. April 2009.
“Human Rights: Political not Theological.” Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association. Chicago, IL. April 2008.
“Coping with Cultural Relativism in the Application of Human Rights.” Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. Chicago, IL. September 2007.
“Carl Schmitt and Constitutional Failure in Weimar Germany.” Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. Washington, DC. September 2005.
“Citizen Rights and Obligations Beyond State Borders: Lessons from the European Union.” Biennial Conference of the European Union Studies Association. Austin, TX. April 2005.
“Responding to Globalization and Political Fragmentation by Softening Identities in State and Society.” Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. Philadelphia, PA. August 2003.
“Decoupling Political Culture from Majority Culture in the Normatively Thin State.” Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. Philadelphia, PA. August 2003.
CURRENT RESEARCH
My current research agenda proceeds along two (at points, intersecting) tracks: political bioethics and human rights as a social science.
Track 1. Political Bioethics
The still relatively new field of bioethics has developed two major, complementary branches: moral analysis and clinical application. My book-in-progress (under contract with Cambridge University Press, forthcoming 2021, titled Creating Human Nature: The Political Challenges of Genetic Enhancement) proposes a third branch that extends the first two with the argument that bioethics is a fundamentally political phenomenon, where the term politics refers to the contestation of different value-commitments and political “success” involves coping well with abiding disagreement. Bioethics thus involves decisions that cannot be “correct” —— but can be procedurally legitimate.
Think of it this way: questions that can have correct answers (even in morally pluralist societies) may not require discussion in the public sphere; rule-following suffices. For example: “Would the subjection of humans to research techniques such as vivisection be ethical?” Such questions are not political.
By contrast, questions that can only be answered in terms of the particular value-commitments of the deciders are political in that answers ideally would be generated through critical discussions —— not only among experts but among members of the general public. For example: “It is permissible to genetically modify humans to enhance normal capabilities?” By experts I mean scientists (who can answer technical questions such as: Is genome editing possible with precision sufficient to create genetically modified babies? I also mean physicians (who can determine if any medical needs are so compelling as to outweigh the risks).
But neither type of expert can address the kinds of questions that a political community (no matter how diverse or fragmented) ideally would contribute to, questions such as: Who has the right to decide? Might routine genome editing alter human societies? Are there dangers of exacerbating already existing social inequalities (the better-off would have greater access), or of economic forces (from “genetic marketplaces” to “genetic fashions”)?
This specifically political bioethics proposes that bioethics should aspire to become a democratic project that involves ordinary citizens as far as reasonably possible.
Table of Contents
- The Political Bioethics of Human Genetic Engineering
- Human Nature as Biotechnological Construction?
- Parents Engineering their Children Genetically
- How Liberal Democratic Societies Can Regulate Human Genetic Engineering
- The Politics of Genetically Engineering Human Intelligence
- Genetic Enhancement of Human Intelligence: Continuum with Conventional
Enhancement or Caesura?
- Personalized Education Tailored to the Pupil’s Genome
- The Political Capacity of Human Intelligence Outsourced to Artificial Intelligence
III. Human Genetic Engineering and Inequality: Within Political Community and Across the Globe
- Creating Equal Citizenship by Means of a Minimum Genetic Capacity
- Deploying Epigenetics to Identify Corporate Responsibility for Health Inequalities
- Human Genetic Engineering and Global Justice in the Anthropocene
- Political Bioethics as a Critical Standard: Evaluating Current Practice in France, the
UK, and Singapore
Coda: Human Genetic Engineering Between Emancipation and Reification
*
Note the particularized research agenda for Chapter 10, which is empirical and requires on-site research overseas. I have completed research in France and the UK and, with a $10,000 Creative Grant from UT VPR Research (and an IRB Exempt Determination from the UT Office of Research Support and Compliance), will conduct interviews in Singapore during the summer of 2021.
Chapter 10 compares three different national approaches to the question: How best does the state regulate genetic technologies able to make heritable changes to the human germline by altering the DNA sequences of embryos? A public, deliberative approach to deciding this difficult and controversial issue is central to the respective approaches of Great Britain and France; it is absent in Singapore.
This “mini-project” completes the third leg of this comparison by evaluating two key features of Singapore’s Bioethics Advisory Committee’s (BAC) approach: (1) subordinating individual interest to group interest (rather than subordinating group interest to individual interest) and (2) a top-down approach (rather than a transparent dialogue with public input). I evaluate each feature by measuring and analyzing (a) levels of public knowledge about this public policy issue and (b) levels of popular embrace or rejection. Measurement draws on standard social scientific practice; analysis draws on moral theory and current bioethical discourse. Given the authoritarian nature of Singapore’s political culture (political dissent and criticism of judicial decisions are not tolerated), my best source of data will be interviews with relevant persons (both inside the BAC as well as outside observers and critics) to elicit candid assessments of the effectiveness of the BAC’s approach.
Track 2. Continuation of: Human Rights as a Social Science
The second track of my current research agenda continues my work in the area of human rights as social science, that is, conceived as social constructs compatible with a naturalist understanding of the world (rather than as otherworldly, theological or metaphysical givens). This agenda has three threads; each develops, along a particular dimension, the idea of human rights as social science.
(a) One thread is connected to my book on political bioethics. Research Agenda: Eighty percent of often incurable conditions affect newborns. Beyond somatic gene therapies (already in clinical trials for spinal muscular atrophy, beta thalassemia, and macular degeneration), germline genome editing may one day erase these scourges. A human rights standpoint confronts competing imperatives. On the one hand, calls for global moratoria on clinical applications of heritable genome editing stifle scientific and political debate on possible ethical forms of treatment and denies children the benefits of advances in genetic science. On the other hand, should the embryo, as a future person, enjoy a “human” right to be free of genetic manipulation to which it has not assented?
(b) A second thread concerns indigenous peoples. I have published articles titled “A Socially Constructed Human Right to the Self-Determination of Indigenous Peoples” (2017); “Indigeneity as Social Construct and Political Tool” (2019); “Against Self-Isolation as a Human Right of Indigenous Peoples in Latin America” (2019); and “The Indigenous Rights State” (2020).
Research Agenda: I have shown that domestic law can advance the project of human rights specific to indigenous peoples. I now seek to show that international law, an underdeveloped means of pursuing indigenous interests, needs both to complement domestic law and to challenge it when (as so often) it fails.
(c) The third strand focuses on developing the potential of multinational corporations to serve as advocates for human rights. To date I’ve developed this strand includes in edited volume chapter, “Human Rights Require yet Contest National Sovereignty: How a Human Rights Corporation Might Help” (2020), and in an article under review: “Beyond Due Diligence: The Human Rights Corporation.”
Research Agenda: I am now exploring five non-governmental organizations that can support corporations in orientation and self-evaluation, concrete standards and evaluations, in a human rights register. First, Norway’s Government Pension Fund Global determines investments in companies on the basis of an evaluation that includes criteria of human rights-relevant ethics. Second, Corporate Human Rights Benchmarks focuses on three high-risk industries (agricultural products, apparel, and extractives) and analyzes the competitive nature of the as a powerful driver for addressing adverse market impacts on employees, consumers, and communities. Third, KnowTheChain targets a particular human rights issue —— forced labor risks within the supply chain —— in sixty of the largest global enterprises in three high-risk sectors: information and communications technology, food and beverage, and apparel and footwear. Fourth, corporations interested in pursuing human rights standards independently can seek out the Danish Institute for Human Rights for advice and counsel. It might reject an enterprise that was unable to demonstrate its commitment to human rights, or that declined to accept DIHR standards of transparency, or was only interested in public relations, or was found to have failed human rights standards when evaluated in a DIHR follow up. Fifth, the Global Reporting Initiative deploys independent standards to help enterprises understand and communicate their environmental, economic and social impacts on issues —— including human rights —— by identifying, gathering, and reporting relevant information.
Courses
GOV 355M • Political Bioethics
38668 • Spring 2021
Meets TTH 3:30PM-5:00PM WAG 101
Wr
UGS 303 • Seeking Justice In Constitutn
62190-62205 • Spring 2021
Meets TTH 5:00PM-6:30PM ECJ 1.202
Wr
ID
S S 302C • Hon Soc Sci:methods/Theory
41015 • Fall 2020
Meets TTH 3:30PM-5:00PM PMA 7.114
SB
UGS 303 • Seeking Justice In Constitutn
61740-61755 • Fall 2020
Meets TTH 5:00PM-6:30PM WCH 1.120
Wr
ID
GOV F335Q • Global Justice-Wb
80674 • Summer 2020
Internet; Asynchronous
Wr
S S 302C • Hon Soc Sci:methods/Theory
41609 • Spring 2020
Meets TTH 3:30PM-5:00PM BEN 1.106
Wr
SB
UGS 303 • Seeking Justice In Constitutn
60120-60135 • Spring 2020
Meets TTH 5:00PM-6:30PM
EWr
ID
GOV 314E • Classics Of Socl/Polit Thought
37504 • Fall 2019
Meets TTH 3:30PM-5:00PM PAR 10
SB
(also listed as CTI 302)
UGS 303 • Seeking Justice In Constitutn
61885-61900 • Fall 2019
Meets MW 4:00PM-5:30PM RLP 0.128
EWr
ID
GOV S335M • Global Justice
81885 • Summer 2019
Meets MTWTHF 8:30AM-10:00AM MEZ B0.302
EWr
GOV 314 • Classics Of Socl/Polit Thou
38190 • Spring 2019
Meets TTH 3:30PM-5:00PM MEZ 1.210
SB
(also listed as CTI 302)
S S 302C • Hon Soc Sci:methods/Theory
42165 • Spring 2019
Meets MW 4:00PM-5:30PM JGB 2.202
Wr
SB
GOV F335M • Global Justice
82650 • Summer 2018
Meets MTWTHF 8:30AM-10:00AM MEZ 2.118
Wr
GOV 335M • Global Justice
38693 • Fall 2017
Meets TTH 5:00PM-6:30PM BEN 1.102
Wr
GOV 382K • Studies In Polit Thry & Philos
38888 • Fall 2017
Meets TH 7:00PM-10:00PM BAT 1.104
S S 301 • Honors Social Science
42752 • Fall 2017
Meets W 5:00PM-8:00PM JGB 2.202
SB
GOV F335M • Global Justice
83022 • Summer 2017
Meets MTTHF 11:30AM-1:00PM CLA 0.102
GOV 335M • Political Philo Of Rousseau
38620 • Spring 2017
Meets TTH 3:30PM-5:00PM MEZ 1.210
Wr
(also listed as CTI 335)
S S 301 • Hon Soc Sci: Soc Sci Theory
42845 • Spring 2017
Meets W 4:00PM-7:00PM GDC 1.406
Wr
SB
UGS 303 • Seeking Justice In Constitutn
63285-63300 • Spring 2017
Meets TTH 5:00PM-6:30PM CLA 0.112
EWr
ID
GOV 335M • Hegel: Formatn Mod Eur Iden
38425 • Fall 2016
Meets MW 4:00PM-5:30PM GAR 3.116
(also listed as CTI 335, EUS 348)
UGS 303 • Seeking Justice/Constitution
63610-63625 • Fall 2016
Meets TTH 5:00PM-6:30PM CLA 0.128
EWr
ID
UGS 303 • Patriotism And Human Rights
62590-62605 • Fall 2015
Meets TTH 5:00PM-6:30PM MEZ B0.306
EWr
ID
GOV S335M • Global Justice
84140 • Summer 2015
Meets MTWTHF 8:30AM-10:00AM MEZ 2.124
E
GOV 314 • Human Rights: Theories/Pracs
38785 • Fall 2014
Meets TTH 9:30AM-11:00AM PAR 203
Wr
(also listed as BDP 319)
S S 301 • Hon Soc Sci: Clas/Contemp Socl
43295 • Fall 2014
Meets TTH 11:00AM-12:30PM PAR 103
Wr
GOV 335M • Hegel: Formatn Of Mod Eur Iden
39115 • Spring 2014
Meets TTH 9:30AM-11:00AM BEN 1.126
(also listed as CTI 335, EUS 348)
GOV 360N • Us-China Relations-Chn
39270 • Spring 2014
GOV 384N • Manipulation Of Human Genome
39470 • Spring 2014
Meets M 7:00PM-10:00PM TNH 3.115
(also listed as LAW 379M, PHL 387)
GOV 335M • Classics Socl Scientif Thought
39147 • Fall 2013
Meets TTH 11:00AM-12:30PM PAR 103
EGCWr
(also listed as CTI 365)
S S 301 • Hon Soc Sci: Clas/Contemp Socl
43335 • Fall 2013
Meets TTH 9:30AM-11:00AM PAR 206
GOV S335M • Global Justice
85185 • Summer 2013
Meets MTWTHF 8:30AM-10:00AM CLA 0.106
E
GOV 335M • Hegel: Formatn Of Mod Eur Iden
38795 • Spring 2013
Meets MW 4:00PM-5:30PM CLA 0.118
(also listed as CTI 335, EUS 348)
GOV 382K • Studies In Polit Thry & Philos
39055 • Spring 2013
Meets TH 7:00PM-10:00PM MEZ 1.104
GOV 314 • Human Rights: Theories/Pracs
38660 • Fall 2012
Meets TTH 9:30AM-11:00AM PAR 301
Wr
(also listed as BDP 319)
S S 301 • Hon Soc Sci: Thry Of Subject
42870 • Fall 2012
Meets TTH 11:00AM-12:30PM GEA 127
Wr
GOV S335M • Global Justice
85363 • Summer 2011
Meets MTWTHF 8:30AM-10:00AM CMA A5.136
EGCWr
GOV 312P • Constitutnl Prins: Core Texts
38820 • Spring 2011
Meets MW 5:00PM-6:30PM PAR 1
GOV 335M • Empire And European Culture
38867 • Spring 2011
Meets MW 3:30PM-5:00PM WAG 308
GCWr
(also listed as CTI 335, EUS 348)
GOV 314 • Human Rights: Theories/Pracs
38502 • Fall 2010
Meets TTH 9:30AM-11:00AM FAC 4
S S 301 • Hon Soc Sci: Soc Sci Theory
42705 • Fall 2010
Meets TTH 11:00AM-12:30PM PAR 303
Wr
C1
GOV S335M • Global Justice-W
84875 • Summer 2010
Meets MTWTHF 8:30AM-10:00AM MEZ 2.124
E
C2
GOV 382M • Early Cosmopolitan Pol Thought
39375 • Fall 2009
Meets T 6:30PM-9:30PM MEZ 1.104
S S 301 • Hon Soc Sci: Soc Sci Theory-W
43645 • Fall 2009
Meets TTH 12:30PM-2:00PM CBA 4.344
C1
GOV 312L • Iss & Policies In Amer Gov-Hon
38140 • Spring 2009
Meets TTH 12:30PM-2:00PM JES A218A
GO
GOV 335M • Global Justice-W
39420 • Fall 2008
Meets TTH 12:30PM-2:00PM MEZ 1.102
C2
GOV 382M • Empire And Early Modern Theory
39655 • Fall 2008
Meets T 6:30PM-9:30PM MEZ 1.104
GOV 312L • Iss & Policies In Amer Gov-Hon
39160 • Spring 2008
Meets TTH 8:00AM-9:30AM MEZ B0.306
GO
GOV 382M • Global Justice
39510 • Spring 2008
Meets TH 7:00PM-10:00PM MEZ 1.104
GOV 335M • Contemporary Political Thry-W
39990 • Fall 2007
Meets TTH 9:30AM-11:00AM CBA 4.336
C2
GOV S312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
86125 • Summer 2007
Meets MTWTHF 11:30AM-1:00PM WEL 2.122
GO
GOV 335M • Contemporary Political Thry-W
38752 • Spring 2007
Meets TTH 9:30AM-11:00AM PMA 7.114
C2
GOV 335M • State Sovereignty/Human Rts-W
38758 • Spring 2007
Meets TTH 12:30PM-2:00PM JES A218A
C2
GOV 312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
39605 • Fall 2006
Meets TTH 8:00AM-9:30AM MEZ 1.306
GO
GOV 335M • State Sovereignty/Human Rts-W
39700 • Fall 2006
Meets TTH 11:00AM-12:30PM BAT 5.102
C2
GOV 379S • Social Theory In Polit Anly-W
38095 • Spring 2006
Meets T 7:00PM-10:00PM CBA 4.340
C2
GOV 382M • State Sovereignty/Human Rights
38125 • Spring 2006
Meets TH 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 214
(also listed as PHL 387)
GOV 312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
37538 • Fall 2005
Meets TTH 9:30AM-11:00AM WCH 1.120
GO
GOV 312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
36190 • Spring 2005
Meets MW 4:30PM-6:00PM MEZ 1.306
GO
GOV 312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
34935 • Spring 2004
Meets TTH 8:00AM-9:30AM GAR 1
GO
GOV 335M • Contemp European Socl Thry-W
35735 • Fall 2003
Meets W 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 436A
C2
(also listed as PHL 365)
GOV 335M • Contemp Amer Social Theory-W
35740 • Fall 2003
Meets TH 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 214
C2
(also listed as PHL 365)
GOV S312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
85510 • Summer 2003
Meets MTWTHF 8:30AM-10:00AM TAY 2.006
GO
GOV 335M • Contemp European Socl Thry-W
34750 • Spring 2003
Meets W 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 602
C2
(also listed as PHL 365)
GOV 312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
35160 • Fall 2002
Meets MW 6:00PM-7:30PM GEA 105
GO
GOV 384N • Social Theories Of Law
35535 • Fall 2002
Meets T 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 128
GOV F312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
85600 • Summer 2002
Meets MTWTHF 10:00AM-11:30AM ART 1.102
GO
GOV 312L • Iss & Policies In Am Gov-Hon-W
34460 • Spring 2002
Meets MWF 11:00AM-12:00PM GAR 3
GO
GOV 335M • Contemp European Socl Thry-W
35790 • Fall 2001
Meets T 7:00PM-10:00PM GEA 127
C2
(also listed as PHL 365)
GOV 384N • Political Community
35995 • Fall 2001
Meets W 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 232
(also listed as PHL 387)
GOV F312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
84980 • Summer 2001
Meets MTWTHF 8:30AM-10:00AM WEL 2.304
GO
GOV 335M • Contemp Amer Social Theory-W
34670 • Spring 2001
Meets T 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 214
C2
(also listed as PHL 365)
GOV 382M • Critical Social Theory
34965 • Spring 2001
Meets W 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 214
(also listed as PHL 387)
GOV F312L • Iss And Policies In Amer Gov
85093 • Summer 2000
Meets MTWTHF 10:00AM-11:30AM WEL 2.308
GO
GOV 382M • Critical Social Theory
34635 • Spring 2000
Meets W 7:00PM-10:00PM BUR 214
(also listed as PHL 387)
Book 2016 ::: The Human Rights State
The Human Rights State
Justice Within and Beyond Sovereign Nations
Benjamin Gregg
288 pages | 6 x 9
Cloth Apr 2016 | ISBN 978-0-8122-4805-0 | $59.95s | £39.00 |
Ebook Apr 2016 | ISBN 978-0-8122-9267-1 | $59.95s | £39.00
A volume in the Pennsylvania Studies in Human Rights series
BELOW: View (a) Table of Contents and (b) Introduction
"The Human Rights State is a compelling contribution to the theory of human rights, ranging from the ontology of such rights to the theoretical articulation of their international and local practice."—Kelvin Knight, London Metropolitan University"The Human Rights State makes a significant contribution to current debates about both the theory and practice of human rights. It will be of interest to philosophers, political theorists, legal scholars, and activists from across the political spectrum."—Martin Woessner, The City College of New York
The nation state operates on a logic of exclusion: no state can offer citizenship and legal rights to all comers. From the logic of exclusion a state derives its sovereign power. Yet this exclusivity undermines the project of advancing human rights globally. That project operates on a logic of inclusion: all people, regardless of citizenship status or territorial location, would everywhere be recognized as bearers of human rights. In practice, human rights are afforded, if at all, then only to citizens of those few states that sometimes regard human rights as moral necessities of domestic commitments—or for states that find that stance politically expedient for the moment.
This discouraging reality in the first decades of the twenty-first century prompts the question: What political arrangement might better conduce the local embrace and enduring practice of human rights? In The Human Rights State, Benjamin Gregg challenges the conviction that the nation state can only have a zero-sum relationship with human rights: national sovereignty is possible or human rights are possible, but not both, not in the same place, at the same time. He argues that the human rights project would be more effective if established and enforced at local levels as locally valid norms, and from there encouraged to expand outward toward overlaps with other locally established and enforced conceptions of human rights grown in their own local soils.
Proposing a metaphorical human rights state that operates within or alongside a nation state, Gregg describes networks of activists that encourage local political and legal systems to generate domestic obligations to enforce human rights. Geographic boundaries and national sovereignties would remain intact but diminished to the extent necessary to extend human rights to all persons, without reservation, across national borders, by rendering human rights an integral aspect of the nation state's constitution.
/ / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / / /
Table of Contents
Introduction. A Project for the Free Embrace of Human Rights
Part I. THE HUMAN RIGHTS STATE: POLITICS BY METAPHOR
Chapter 1. Human Rights as Metaphor
Chapter 2. Human Rights in a Backpack
Chapter 3. The Body as Human Rights Boundary
PART II. THE HUMAN RIGHTS STATE THROUGH PERSUASION, NOT COERCION
Chapter 4. Teaching Human Rights as a Cognitive Style
Chapter 5. Developing Human Rights Commitment in Post-Authoritarian Societies
Chapter 6. Digital Technology as Resource for the Human Rights Project
PART III. DEFENSE OF THE HUMAN RIGHTS STATE IN THE FACE OF CHALLENGES
Chapter 7. Human Rights Patriotism
Chapter 8. A Human Right Not to Democracy but to the Rule of Law
Chapter 9. Human Rights and Humanitarian Intervention
Coda: A Community of Nation States Practicing Domestic Cosmopolitanism
Notes
References
Index
Acknowledgments
Excerpt [uncorrected, not for citation]
Introduction: A Project for the Free Embrace of Human Rights
The playwright Bertolt Brecht spent fourteen years in exile. He was officially stateless for twelve. He fled Germany in February 1933, one month after the Nazis took power. After shorter stays in various cities, including Prague, Vienna, Zürich, and Paris, he spent a longer period in Denmark and then in Sweden. When the Germans occupied Denmark and attacked Norway in 1940, and neutral Sweden allowed Germany transit routes for its Norwegian campaign, Brecht fled in April to Finland by ship. He remained in Finland until May 1941, when he left by train for Leningrad, then Moscow, then Vladivostok and, only nine days before the Nazis invaded the Soviet Union, by Swedish boat to Los Angeles, which he reached in July. He returned to Europe in 1947.
While he and his companions struggled to get visas to the United States, Brecht started a play in rural Marlebäck, four hours outside Helsinki, in 1940, and worked on it intermittently until 1944, in Los Angeles. He sets his Flüchtlingsgespräche, orConversations in Exile, in a bar at the Helsinki Railway Station where two German refugees, Ziffel, a physicist, and Kalle, a laborer, while away their time sparring in a loosely connected series of meandering exchanges. "These encompass memories of childhood and school years as well as of exile, some of which . . . are recognizable as Brecht's own" (Parker 2014:421). At one point Ziffel says to Kalle, "The passport is the noblest part of a person. It isn't generated in the plain and simple way people are. A person can be begotten anywhere in the world, in the most frivolous of ways—but not a passport. That's why a passport, so long as it's a good one, is recognized—whereas a person can be ever so good yet still be denied recognition." Brecht captures in this passage the topsy-turvy world of rights: what matters is not the human being but rather his or her legal status. Thus the person is reduced to an epiphenomenon of a formal document issued by a nation state. And a passport assumes some of the qualities usually attributed instead to human beings: nobility; grounds for social and legal recognition; the bearer of "goodness" and "badness."
This book offers a critique of this topsy-turvy logic. It then develops an alternative logic. This "inclusionary logic" is a vision not of rights in general but of human rights in particular. It has several core features. Consider each in turn.
Social Construction as Method
This book takes forward a project I began in Human Rights as Social Construction. There I argue for human rights as worldly social constructions. Human rights in this context may take any number of overlapping forms, from the "human rights idea" to the "human rights project," from "human rights thinking" to "human rights communities," as well as human rights themselves.
To say that human rights are socially constructed is to regard them wholly as products of human imagination. It is to regard them as this-worldly products of human hand, as distinguished from otherworldly givens, whether theological or metaphysical.
This is a rather optimistic view. It is the conviction that we humans can pull ourselves up morally by our own normative bootstraps. It is the belief that communities can assume the stance of active producers of their fate rather than regarding themselves as passive "consumers" of otherworldly givens.
To say that human communities invent moralities is to say that moralities are cultural claims. In this sense I regard human rights as political phenomena, as a matter of political agency, toward social justice. Ideas of justice, behaviors that create and reinforce justice, and institutions that provide justice—for example, by treating all members of society as legal and moral equals—do not start out as universals. They start out as particular expressions of agency. They begin as historically and culturally particular. And they are always embedded in socially constructed structures: cultural traditions, philosophical schools, social mores, legal systems. This book seeks to show how, in the longue durée, human rights as political phenomena can aspire to eventual universal purchase. The idea of a human rights state is a means of advancing a realistic cosmopolitanism.
As social constructions, human rights are contingent norms. That is, their validity depends on humans regarding them as valid. To construe the validity of human rights as relative to the humans who construct them is to view human rights in their element of moral relativism. It is to view them in their medium of historical and cultural perspectivalism. It is to view them as essentially "political" in nature. A specificallypolitical social construction is a contingent, this-worldly idea. Its moral potential cannot be harvested unless it is always open to contestation, reinterpretation, and adaptation. Its moral potential needs a community open to negotiation and compromise in the effort to achieve agreement among participants on matters of human rights. The forging and reforging of agreement on human rights can still lead to a nonidiosyncratic perspective. In a postmetaphysical landscape, a nonidiosyncratic perspective replaces what religion and metaphysics regard as perspectives true or valid universally or a priori or eternally.
A nonidiosyncratic perspective is true or valid because it is held consensually, not because it is inherently neutral or acultural or transcendent. And if the validity of human rights is contingent, fallibilistic, and locally embedded, truth and justice at any given time refer to a temporary report from the field of experience and inquiry, a "snapshot" for current orientation, always revisable. Understood in this relativist sense, truth and justice are neither impossible nor drained of their capacity to motivate behavior. Rather, both truth and justice are driven not by some epistemological imperative for objectivity but by a pragmatic imperative for desired results. As social constructions, human rights are not some absolute or timeless cornerstone for moral theory. They are a "rhetorical vehicle" that can convey various meanings under different circumstances and can serve multiple purposes in different contexts. Among these meanings and purposes are elements of justice, such as rights to life, safety, and personal liberty; to belief, expression, and conscience; to privacy and property.
On this approach, human rights are one more example of what human culture can imagine. While their historical achievement would be an extraordinary event in human history, human rights are not themselves something special or extraordinary. They are not the work of extraordinary individuals or groups, and the most common people in the most ordinary of circumstances can imagine and create them. They do not require any special way of thinking. They work with readily understandable intuitions, such as the moral usefulness of putting oneself in the other's shoes. They work with well-known ideas such as "prudential reciprocity," which motivates behavior along the lines of mutual benefit. Such mundane characteristics mark potential for beginning to develop a human rights consciousness in almost any community in which people can be motivated to practice reciprocity and are capable of putting themselves in the other's shoes.
Yet social construction is not just one more comprehensive view. It can coexist with a wide range of competing comprehensive doctrines. For example, it can cooperate with persons of faith who share the goal of advancing human rights. Regardless of its empirical, secular orientation within the social sciences, my proposal in no way seeks to dissuade the faithful from their faith. Even as I reject "theological and metaphysical foundations of human rights as counterproductive," I dismiss neither insofar as either offers an "important way for some people in some communities to access human rights language" (Wolfsteller 2014:496).
To dismiss any particular motivations to an embrace of human rights would defeat my pragmatic orientation. That orientation emphasizes the search for resources for advancing human rights. Resources might be found in some elements of local culture and experience. Further, human rights are best implemented from within the local community. And the local community best implements them. They are best implemented in terms that resonate as much as possible with that community—even as human rights also challenge the community to reimagine beliefs and practices in ways more human rights friendly.
Non-social-constructionist presuppositions, such as religious faith, can work in tandem with the social constructionism they reject, and that I advocate as more practicable and generalizable. They can work in tandem toward the same goal: to encourage a free embrace of human rights. Social construction does not require addressees of the human rights project to adopt a social-constructionist standpoint. (By human rights project I mean the project of advancing human rights globally, through persuasion. As foraddressees, I focus on the citizens of nation states, as I explain below.) Social construction can reach individuals and communities without having to abandon, wholesale, their thick normative commitments. After all, most persons invested in supernatural revelation also accept claims of a very different sort—for example, those that lead to standard medical diagnosis and treatment.
One might argue that if transcendental norms can only be the product of imagination, then I am no less dogmatic than my adversaries, for example, the legal philosopher Michael Perry (2007). One might argue to the same conclusion if, as I assert, the moral self-ennoblement of human beings is precisely that of humankind giving itself norms of social and political behavior. Perry asserts that human rights are only coherent given a belief in God and in the "sacredness" of human beings. I counter that social constructions are not necessarily exclusive whereas every religion is. Even as it is hardly acultural, or presuppositionless, or unembedded in history and culture, social construction is never as particular as any argument grounded in revelation. It can work with rival approaches to human rights.
A Wholly Naturalistic Conception of Human Beings
I approach the human in the phrase human rights in terms of a wholly naturalistic conception of humanity. That conception takes human nature as biologically understood. It eschews supernatural explanations, whether theological or metaphysical. To be sure, human nature biologically understood guarantees nothing in a political way or otherwise in a value-driven sense. It entails nothing normative. Human rights, for example, cannot be derived from natural facts. That the genome of any one human individual can represent the genome of the species entails no moral norms, and the similarity of one person's DNA to another's entails no moral or legal obligations of one to the other.
A naturalistic approach to the human of human rights proceeds along several dimensions. Consider two. Consider the fact that all humans share the same genome. No one should be surprised if someone were inspired to give this fact a cultural overlay, perhaps in ways suggestive for the social construction of norms. For example, most human rights abusers identify their victims in terms of their membership in particular groups (religion, race, or caste, among others). In this context, the human rights idea could be advanced if at least some abusers come to realize that such memberships are in fact constructions. By contrast, the species-wide genetic identity of all individuals is not. To be sure, this biological "is" generates no normative "ought." But it opens up a human rights-friendly vantage point that will resonate with some people.
Second, cultural agreements on human rights can draw on natural emotional dispositions as a resource. That is, "natural" altruism can be fostered and institutionalized by cultural means, in various forms of socialization. Elsewhere I draw on research in neurobiology to suggest that mutualism and altruism are biological dispositions. They can be harnessed by various kinds of socialization. In this way they encourage sympathy and understanding for the idea of human rights. One kind of socialization, supported by a kind of "sentimental education" found in European intellectual history, encourages solidarity. It could buttress rationally motivated practices of solidarity based on human rights.
To be sure, some emotional dispositions are incompatible with human rights thinking. And most dispositions are complex enough to go in more than one direction. For example, sympathy for one's own tribe hardly entails barbarism toward other tribes—but it could serve such a basis. Where dispositions are compatible or even supportive of human rights thinking, they provide a standpoint—an internal standpoint, not imposed from outside—from which to identify human rights abuses. They provide a standpoint for identifying these abuses as they occur in behavior allowed or even encouraged in other areas of the same religion, culture, or tradition.
Such dispositions will never do the work that human rights advocates might hope for. Nor will another possible resource for advancing human rights thinking that I mentioned earlier: prudential reciprocity. But the fact that a particular resource cannot guarantee success, or that it might be deployed contrary to human rights, is a fact about the limitations of resources. To abandon resources if they cannot guarantee success, or guarantee against misuse, would be self-defeating.
Human Rights Advanced Through Persuasion, Not Coercion
Because human rights, like all moral norms, are social constructions, they can only be valid for their addressees if those addressees freely, self-reflexively come to embrace them. A free embrace is truly free only if it occurs not only at a communal level but at the level of individual members as well. Embracing human rights in this way requires institutionalized socialization. If these norms become entrenched in a community's social institutions—such as the legal order and public education—they in turn reinforce the development of individual human rights personalities. They will do so by socializing people into a solidarity based on the mutual expectation: local participants grant themselves human rights, and they mutually recognize each other's self-grants. Some cultural and psychological processes of cultural socialization offer resources here. For example, socialization into assertive selfhood is a cultural and historical process that endows addressees with the psychological wherewithal and self-confidence to claim human rights for themselves.
Socialization into assertive selfhood does not entail homogeneity. It does not lead to homogeneity as a homogeneous identity shared by all members of a political community. It generates no homogenizing, universally shared belief in some particular cultural construction of "human nature." It requires no world state unifying the plethora of competing cultures any world state would encompass. (I evaluate the idea of a world state, and alternatives to it, in the Coda.) On the contrary, members of a highly individuated society are integrated through "difference" rather than "identity." Georg Simmel showed as much more than a century ago. Social integration in complex modern societies involves individuals constantly weaving themselves into multiple "webs of affiliation" through interaction with members of a range of different social groups. Webs raise awareness for the interests and feelings of others as "others" and, despite all their differences, both group-based differences and differences among individuals. Simmel shows that webs of affiliation increase difference among persons rather than decreasing it. The individual increasingly differentiates him- or herself as the number of affiliations increases.
Someone socialized into assertive selfhood acquires the capacity to author his or her own human rights. To claim rights is the first step toward eventually gaining them, and assertive selfhood both reflects and motivates this moral autonomy. The human rights project facilitates the development of a personality structure of assertive selfhood. That project is one of collective political action. As such, it is one more resource for helping individuals develop assertive selfhood and a human rights personality. In part, the individual develops by recognizing others in their self-granting activity. And he or she develops by collectively challenging nation state- authorities to recognize and respect the self-granted human rights. This book is an extended argument for developing these kinds of activities, collectively, in a human rights state.
A human rights state would remedy the topsy-turvy world of rights that Brecht captures so well in Flüchtlingsgespräche. One element is the participant with his or her human rights personality able (in concert with others) to authorize and grant him- or herself human rights independently of a nation state's legal and political institutions. Such a personality is not necessarily "based on inner consistency, rational insight into the primacy of moral norms as well as a high level of self-reflexivity" (Wolfsteller 2014:496). A pragmatist approach can work with the cognitive and moral inconsistencies of real human beings. A localist approach is sensitive to the "historical specificity of political events and institutions" (ibid., 496). It is attuned to the power that inflects social institutions and relations.
Brecht makes the point that humans do not possess rights independently of nation states. He makes the point that nation states not individuals determine who is worthy of legal status, deserving of rights. He employs the Marxian trope of people reduced to behaving like things and things elevated to behaving like people: the person is reduced to an epiphenomenon of a formal document issued by a nation state. The passport, not the passport bearer, has status and influence on the border between two states.
But the point is not that laws are bad as such but that good law is law that serves human beings by empowering them rather than abusing human beings by excluding them from legal status. The notion of the human rights state is a way to solve the problem that Brecht captures in the case of the exile, the refugee, and the stateless person. And the device of the human rights state solves the problem for citizens of nation states that do not recognize human rights as well. For the idea of a human rights state is the idea of transforming nation states that do not recognize human rights into ones that do. Transformation proceeds through the political advocacy of common people who together would form a particular human rights state. The ultimate goal of political advocacy is a type of juridification just the opposite of Brecht's topsy-turvy world.
The ultimate goal is for these self-granted human rights to find recognition by nation states. They need state recognition to realize their aspiration to stable, consistent, and permanent validity that is effective in practical ways. The goal of juridifying human rights within a nation state (a topic I return to in the Coda) is the opposite of fetishizing law to the detriment of humans. Juridified, human rights will do the most to help people at the bottom of social hierarchies and oppressed minorities and socially marginalized groups to find or create protection from mistreatment. Activists who deploy human rights as a moral language to win for themselves the human rights they want is a primary step along this path. The ultimate step, to be reached in the distant future and only after much hard work and not inconsiderable good fortune, is to win, in part through the role played by the human rights state advocated in this book, human rights within a nation state.
Toward a Universal Embrace of Human Rights as a Contingent, Historical Achievement
To locate the validity of human rights in their addressees rather than in some global institution (if not in some otherworldly source) might seem to forfeit the aspiration of human rights to universal validity. But I argue that universal validity so construed does not forfeit that aspiration. I argue that it circumvents the metaphysical limbo of intractable debates over nature, source, contents, and entailments of human rights. That limbo generates puzzlements, not answers. It offers no techniques for application in the field of advancing human rights across national borders and across the globe. In fact, it works against the human rights project by leading to positions that exclude some groups of people from human rights.
Approaches across a wide spectrum of understandings of social justice all deploy exclusion as one means of identifying those who qualify for social justice or fuller forms of social justice. Consider five examples. The sociological theorist Niklas Luhmann (1998:1023) asserts that two people who are cognitively unequal—because one can reason better than the other—are, as a consequence, morally unequal as well. He who reasons better is, by virtue of superior reasoning, better able to guide his life by the normative principles of human rights. For the most prominent theorist of political liberalism in the late twentieth century, John Rawls (1993:41, 70-73), "outlaw regimes" exclude themselves from the rule of "reasonable and just law" and are justly vulnerable to intervention by liberal peoples. Jean-François Lyotard (1993:135, 141-142), who defines postmodernism as a "fatigue with grand narratives," regards freedom of expression as the single most fundamental human right. Man excludes himself from this right until he frees himself from "his animal nature" by subjecting himself to the civilizing formation of culture. Amitai Etzioni (2010), a prominent advocate of communitarianism, identifies people within liberal democratic communities who exclude themselves from human rights, indeed from all normative insight, because they are mentally ill or incline to the ideological distortions of popular culture or of fermented liquors or other chemical substances.
By contrast with these various approaches, my social-constructionist method follows alogic of inclusion. It renders human rights more accessible than anything offered by these alternatives. Social construction can do so because it allows local participants, by their own best lights, to develop human rights, and to do so locally. One chronic barrier to advancing human rights—abiding differences within and among communities, traditions, economies, political regimes, and ways of thinking—falls away for a method that begins locally and expands outward toward partial overlaps with other locally originating projects for human rights.
For what could be more inclusive than recognizing the human rights project as one in which, in principle, any person, anywhere, at any time, can participate? A project of potentially universal participation is a project of (socially constructed) universal content, a project of (socially constructed) universal validity—universal at least in potential. But this universal project is not universal because it is in any sense otherworldly. On the contrary, it advances human rights in ways entirely this-worldly. This-worldly are social constructions that can be undertaken by the participants themselves. Participants first need to be persuaded that they are capable of authoring their own human rights. Then they need to mutually recognize, within the group, their self-granted rights. At that point participants seek to expand those rights into the corresponding nation state. Self-authorship and expansion outward proceed through persuasion, not coercion. Persuasion takes many forms. This book emphasizes socialization, especially different types of education.
Participants Need Not Agree on All Aspects of Human Rights
Persuasion to freely embrace human rights does not require participants to overcome all their differences in belief and perspective. Complete agreement is empirically unlikely anyway, given the sheer complexity of the human rights idea. It is doubtful given the deep interpretability of so many of its terms and presuppositions. More important, persuasion need not place hurdles in the way of adherents of very different traditions who nonetheless might be persuaded to embrace one or the other idea of human rights. I agree with the spirit captured in a well-known characterization of the various members of the committee that drafted the United Nations' Universal Declaration of Human Rights: "we agree about the rights but on condition no one asks us why" (Glendon 2001:77). Agreement on some rights, in some applications, is enough to make progress; agreement on possible foundations is not necessary.
My project is not motivated by some prior commitment to human rights. It begins with the bare idea of human rights, at first quite indeterminate in meaning. Nor does it start with some agreed-on basis for human rights. It couldn't because the idea of human rights, as long as it is indeterminate in meaning, cannot involve bases. My project is guided by a pragmatic imperative for desired results. The pragmatist goal is not for everyone to agree on a foundation for human rights; the goal is for participants to be able to freely embrace and practice human rights on whatever basis, directed by whatever theory, given whatever presuppositions. This approach generates commitment rather than presupposing it.
Drawing on the spirit of a social scientific account of human rights, I do not believe that a commitment to human rights must be grounded in anything further than an intuition about justice, an interest in justice, a motivation to do justice. I do not believe that ultimate justification for people's normative convictions need lie outside and beyond human imagination and agency. Entirely unnecessary is divine intervention or metaphysical landscape, in either case waiting to be discovered by special minds. I seek a view compatible with social science, one that views human rights as something made not found. Social construction is such a standpoint. It investigates the ways that humans invent their normative grounds and have always invented their normative grounds. It assumes that any normative grounds whatsoever can only be invented by particular groups in particular cultures and contexts over time, usually modified and remodified and reinterpreted by successive groups as long as those norms have current purchase and have not become relegated to no more than an entry in history books. From a social scientific perspective, when it comes to practical guidelines for moral behavior—including human rights-oriented behavior—humans can rely on nothing but their own collective constructions.
All addressees of any human rights whatsoever can and should participate in the articulation, interpretation, and deployment of human rights. Doing so involves constructing, discussing, interpreting, and vernacularizing the human rights idea. It is the work of ordinary people, in democratic communities as well as in nondemocratic communities, influencing public culture. As I have already emphasized, participants are unlikely to agree on all points. They are more likely to generate a range of variation in their understandings, definitions, interpretations, and ideas about deployment. But consensus is not necessary for participants to form a group that is coherent in its self-understanding and adequately motivated. These very differences, generated by the participants themselves, are signal aspects of a self-determining political community that recognizes as legitimate both the process and the nonconsensual outcome. A process involving free expression and free association is, of course, much easier to realize in democratic communities. But sometimes it can also be possible in some nondemocratic communities. It does not require that all political communities be the same. It does not presuppose a world community. It does not undermine the current world system of nation states. But it certainly challenges all nation states from a human rights perspective.
Disharmony and disagreement can, in some cases, be useful and productive. The human rights project, like any nondogmatic normative project, must be fallibilistic, hence an open-ended quest, anticipating a more just world to come even as it can never completely or quickly realize that which it anticipates. For reassurance and guidance as to what rights are and justice is (rather than to anything not socially constructed), this project can only refer to humans themselves, not to gods or transcendental principles.
To be sure, it always matters a great deal if participants disagree about how best to identify, define, and apply human rights and about how to reconcile competing rights. (Thus Chapter 8 argues against construing democracy as a human right but is open to working alongside other human rights advocates who insist that democracy must be a human right.) The human rights project makes progress wherever participants can forge overlaps among competing belief systems. It achieves progress with each enlargement, however limited, of overlapping beliefs and commitments to human rights. Andrew Koppelman (2014:380) well grasps this point:
People with different metaphysical assumptions can and sometimes do converge on the same principles of human rights, but each of them gets there by reference to her own comprehensive view. This is what John Rawls had in mind when he argued for an "overlapping consensus" on the principles of political cooperation. In an overlapping consensus, [participants] may disagree about the ultimate foundations of the political principles that govern them, but they agree upon the principles, those principles are moral ones, and they are affirmed on moral grounds.
The Human Rights State
Human Rights as Social Construction ends with a proposal for a "human rights state." It seeks to replace the nation state with a human rights state. By contrast, The Human Rights State does not propose an alternative to the nation state but rather its modification, namely the diminution of its territorial sovereignty to an extent necessary to make human rights possible as a domestically anchored institution, indeed as an aspect internal to its national constitution. This shift has two motivations. First, replacing the nation state with an alternative is exceedingly unlikely empirically. Correspondingly, doing away with nationalism (as Human Rights as Social Construction proposes) would be more difficult that modifying nationalism into a human rights-nationalism (which The Human Rights State attempts). To be sure, only some nation states might be capable of this modification, and such a development would represent a great advance in the human rights project even if that development were hardly universal. Second, the nation state need not intrinsically preclude human rights if it can be modified in the extent of its sovereignty. So The Human Rights State views the nation state, and several of its core features, as resources for advancing the human rights project, if those features might be modified in various ways, many of which I detail throughout the book.
In this book, by human rights state I mean a metaphorical polity constituted by interested, self-selected members of a corresponding nation state. Members constitute themselves as a human rights state by authoring their own human rights and mutually recognizing that authorship among themselves. A human rights state seeks to advance a free embrace of human rights in the corresponding nation state. It seeks to advance human rights as an internal feature of the nation state, in short, to encourage local political and legal systems to generate domestic legal obligations to abide by human rights. By way of introduction to this notion, I first distinguish a metaphorical human rights state from the state and the nation state. Then I sketch the tense relationship between a human rights state and the corresponding nation state. Finally, I characterize the human rights state in terms of practical strategies toward justice without borders.
A Metaphorical Human Rights State as Distinguished from the State and Nation State
By metaphor I mean a polity of the imagination, a polity without territorial component because it exists in the minds and behaviors of the participants. They practice their self-granted human rights among themselves as a model and example for the corresponding nation state. While one cannot be a member of a metaphor, one can be a member of a political initiative or social movement, one guided by principles. I do not advocate a metaphorical understanding of human rights; I advocate metaphor as a device for practical effect. I propose a metaphorical understanding to be realized in the world, in relation to a state.
Neither political institution nor legal system, a human rights state constitutes a critical moral standard. As a critical moral standard, the human rights state is more than an idea; it is political initiative. Its makeup is unusual: activists united in promoting human rights within the corresponding nation state, activists who mutually recognize each other's human rights, activists who practice human rights among themselves and in their relations with others. It is a social, indeed political, organization that displays patterned behavior and is guided by certain rules.
By state, as distinguished from a nation state in particular, I mean an apparatus primarily bureaucratic-administrative: the legally defined organization of divided powers and formal procedures for deciding everything from political representation to public policy to tax collection. By contrast, a nation state embraces the pre-political solidarity generators of blood and ethnicity, or language and religion, or beliefs about a shared fate, or some combination, perhaps with other generators as well. The correspondence between a territorialized state and a population geographically bounded defines membership in a nation state. That correspondence constitutes a "nation." Many members belong to a particular nation on the basis of their territorial nationality. To belong means not only to identify with that territory, individually and together with others, but also, in some cases, to derive specific rights and duties from it. Inclusion in a nation always entails the exclusion of nonmembers.
A human rights state aspires to global institutions that leave a great deal of administrative and other matters to sovereign states, while internationalizing the recognition and defense of human rights even against offending sovereign states. A community of human rights states (which I sketch in the Coda) could one day culminate in the creation of global institutions that would leave a great deal of administrative and other matters to sovereign states but that would internationalize the recognition and defense of human rights.
The Tense Relationship Between a Human Rights State and the Corresponding Nation State
Ideally there would be one human rights state corresponding to each nation state in the world (or corresponding to other forms of governance where the nation state is not the primary locus of power, such as tribes or corporations). But the possibility of even one human rights state does not require that every last state embrace human rights.
A state that already observes human rights is not itself a human rights state. Such a state does not need a human rights state precisely because it already observes rights. The human rights state is a means to encourage a nation state to adopt these rights.
I imagine many different human rights states. Each would have its particular membership. Each, its distinct range of understandings of human rights. Each, embedded in its local cultural contexts. Each, a critical moral standard by which to measure the corresponding nation state with respect to human rights recognition and adherence. Thus the members of any particular human rights state do not include all of humanity. But if all nation states embraced the human rights advocacy of the corresponding human rights states, all of humanity would be members of a human rights community.
A human rights state stands in tense relation to a nation state. Tensions persist between a nation state and a human rights state as long as the nation state resists the human rights state's efforts to get the nation state to adopt cosmopolitan human rights as one of its regular, internal, domestic features.
A given human rights state is formed primarily of citizens of a corresponding nation state, and a given human rights state stands in the greatest tension with a corresponding nation state that rejects human rights altogether. Citizenship in the corresponding nation state is no requirement for membership in the human rights state. But for practical reasons most members of the human rights state likely will be citizens of the corresponding nation state.
The Human Rights State in Terms of Practical Strategies Toward Justice Without Borders
I support my proposal for human rights states with an array of practical strategies of solidary groups within a nation state seeking to diminish nation state sovereignty to the extent necessary for human rights to become valid across and despite national boundaries. I sketch these strategies in the chapter-by-chapter overview below.
To be sure, a human rights state cannot deliver anyone, or any nation state, directly from the myriad, often-intractable problems of modern political community. It cannot create conflict-free political communities or untroubled trans-state relations. It cannot end the constant need for social, political, and legal struggles, or for negotiations and compromises at all levels of political community. But it can contribute to making human rights more widely available in a world of nation states. It can do so even as it implies no single modality of membership in political community, nor a uniform one. It contributes to an abiding aspiration of a realistic utopia of universal human rights.
That utopian vision begins with the hunch that human rights can be a mundane, everyday political movement of ordinary persons in many places (if not everywhere equally, and not at all times). To be sure, some political environments make human rights advocacy very dangerous; others suggest its utter futility. This book works this hunch into an insight by reimagining state sovereignty as compatible with sovereignty-defying human rights. It decouples the having of rights from the territory that today is generally the condition of having rights. It displaces to the individual the bordering functions of the nation state. The ultimate goal of what could eventually become an international movement of human rights states is justice without borders, an aspect of universal justice. This book adumbrates elements of one path to that goal. But justice without borders is not a world without borders. It is a world of borders modified to permit human rights within nation states.
Chapter-by-Chapter Overview
The three chapters that make up Part I develop key features of a human rights state. Chapter 1 urges an idea of human rights that members of a group would grant to themselves within or alongside a particular nation state. Chapter 2 frames human rights as deterritorialized in a way historically unprecedented: they would obtain in the person of a human being rather than, as now, because he or she happens to stand on a particular territory that happens to embrace human rights. Chapter 3 renders human rights, now reconceived, as a protective boundary displaced from the nation state to the human body.
Consider now each of these chapters in detail. Chapter 1 develops the notion of a human rights state along six dimensions: first, as a metaphor; second, as plural in number, with different human rights states overlapping with each other; third, each human rights state is capable of constructing human rights as "status functions" with "deontic power"; fourth, these functions and powers effectively deterritorialize human rights; fifth, each human rights state exists alongside a corresponding nation state and alongside international organizations; finally, different human rights states together form an international political community, not a world state but a kind of Kantian federation.
Chapter 2 unfolds one of the ways in which the members of a human rights state constitute it. It displaces the locus of rights from national territory to individual participants. This chapter transfers the basis of human rights from national, territorial belonging to human action and political performance. Then it explains how individuals would be motivated to participate in a human rights state. Third, it explicates participation in part as the donning of a "human rights backpack." It ends by analyzing citizenship in a human rights state as the nonformalized power of its participants, a power not tied to the nation state.
Chapter 3 examines the failure of territorialized citizenship to protect against enslavement and the nonterritorial alternative. Then it considers the single most important route to diminishing slavery—namely, reducing poverty—and considers various difficulties involved in poverty reduction. To facilitate progress in the face of these difficulties, it develops a procedure parallel to the backpack of Chapter 2. It proposes construing the human body (and the bodies of slaves, in particular) as analogous to political territory and it proposes displacing boundaries from nation state to the body of the human rights bearer. It proposes construing the body as its own bordering capacity. It deploys this model by criticizing nation state territory that cannot or does not prevent slavery. It criticizes nation state territory on the basis of a different kind of territory: the moral territory of the self. It then works out three respects in which the body as symbol challenges nonprotective citizenship. And it shows how this model can internationalize domestic opposition to slavery.
Three chapters compose Part II. They deploy the metaphor of a human rights state as a politics of persuasion, not coercion. They deploy this metaphor in three widely divergent venues: Chapter 4, in a university curriculum; Chapter 5, in post-authoritarian Eastern Europe; Chapter 6, in the rapidly developing digital technology. In greater detail: Chapter 4 explores ways in which Western youth at university can develop and deploy thinking about human rights as a cognitive style. A cognitive style oriented on human rights rests on two presuppositions: that human rights are social constructions and hence that they are morally relativist and perspectival. The chapter shows how human rights, in terms of a cognitive style, might approach the practice of child labor in general and child-labor-encouraging aspects of poor agrarian communities in particular. Then it specifies normative bases of a human rights style, bases that emerge from its analysis.
Chapter 5 turns to informal, political education in the newly democratizing countries of Eastern Europe. Emphasizing the importance of path dependency for the possible success of a civic education driven by a human rights cognitive style, it analyzes the role of several institutions in developing potential for a human rights culture. First it develops an approach to human rights advocacy by building on the notion of cognitive style introduced in the previous chapter. Then it situates that notion in the context of civic education. Third, it considers forms of civic education toward encouraging active civic participation. Finally, it sketches three models that deploy this approach in diverse educational settings in liberalizing communities today.
Chapter 6 extends the concern with how the human rights project can be advanced by examining the human rights potential of uncoupling, in cyberspace, the individual's social and political identity from his or her social and political voice. First it identifies the Internet's general potential to advance human rights, as well as some of the problems that discourage that potential. In particular, the Internet can advance the cause of human rights by changing civil society by means of digital abstraction from human bodies and national borders. It can advance human rights also by facilitating critical public opinion. The chapter then limns the parameters of possible Internet contributions to the human rights state. The last section examines the intersection of culture and nature in digital technology.
Part III, made up of the last three chapters, addresses several of the challenges faced by the human rights state. Chapter 7 asks: How can someone swear allegiance to both a national identity and the cosmopolitan identity of human rights? Chapter 8 asks: If democratic communities are distinctly friendlier toward the human rights idea than are nondemocratic communities, is democracy itself a condition for the possibility of human rights—in a world much of which is decidedly nondemocratic? And Chapter 9: Can human rights ever be advanced through humanitarian military interventions, even in cases of grave human rights abuses?
Consider each in greater detail. Chapter 7 rejects arguments that regard human rights and patriotism as somehow naturally or internally compatible. It combines the conviction that human rights require a political, territorial space with the conviction that motivation in political community is unlikely absent emotional affect. It combines these convictions by making the human rights point of view integral to a citizen's point of view as a citizen. It does so first by developing human rights patriotism as a politics of metaphor that, second, leads to a transnational patriotism that, third, is a constitutionally supported attachment both national and cosmopolitan.
Chapter 8 shows how the rule of law advances human rights globally more effectively than democracy. It shows that, however ambitious it is in some nation states, it is less ambitious than the development of democracy. To determine what might best be constructed locally as a human right, it proposes the capacity of the candidate norm to be freely embraced by its addressees. It then argues that the rule of law is the better alternative to constructing democracy as a human right. Third, it examines the noncosmopolitan quality of democracy, as well as the rule of law and the possibility of self-determination even in the absence of democracy. Finally, toward advancing the human rights project, it proposes the legalism not of democracy but of the rule of law.
Chapter 9 asks: From a human rights standpoint, what conditions of brutality and oppression justify coercive intervention in a sovereign nation state? To answer this question it addresses the goal of humanitarian intervention as well as the paradoxical status of state sovereignty. Then it argues that sovereignty is necessary for human rights and suggests a realistic understanding of state sovereignty in the context of humanitarian intervention. It then advocates a human rights minimalism, one neither value neutral nor nonpartisan: the minimalist goal of intervention is to stop the killing, nothing more. For intervention cannot do the work that only domestic politics can do, including the work of a human rights state. The chapter argues for unilateralism rather than multilateralism in most cases. It finds no universal a priori responsibility to protect.
A brief coda sketches one urgent area for future work: the problems and prospects of a community of nation states, each member having constitutionalized human rights domestically. An association of members sharing a domestic commitment to human rights revises contemporary notions of both national sovereignty and political territoriality. And, not least, it reworks the normative grammar of statehood in terms of domestic cosmopolitanism.
Yale Interdisciplinary Center for Bioethics 2016
RESEARCH PROJECT TITLE
“Human Nature as Cultural Design: The Political Challenge of Genetic Engineering”
DESCRIPTION
As a Yale-Hastings Visiting Scholar in the summer of 2016, I will develop, and discuss with my fellow scholars in Hastings Institute (Garrison, N.Y.) and at Yale, an initial draft of the core idea of the first three chapters of a book manuscript titled “Human Nature as Cultural Design: The Political Challenge of Genetic Enhancement."
The manuscript develops a reciprocal, co-constitutive relationship between biotechnology and the legal and moral norms of liberal democratic political communities (and considers possible relationships in some kinds of non-democratic communities). Ideally, such political communities would respond dynamically to changes in the environments created by advances in biotechnology. Ideally, they would do so in line with moral norms and positive laws animated by a new kind of moral thinking, one fitted to a biotechnological age: moral and legal norms that are dynamic not static, relativist not absolutist. A political community’s on-going evaluation of different forms of genetic engineering might then be accompanied by a different form of engineering, engineering of a normative kind, a new kind of normative thinking, one that meets the political challenges of genetic engineering.
I imagine a new kind of normative thinking in place of the current normative impasse in thinking, where no particular understanding of the proper goals and functions of genetic engineering can provide guidance beyond this or that sliver of cultural preference. That is, normative guidance is hard to come by given that no community today shares a single conception of what might constitute desirable genetic manipulations. Any given framing of the “enhanceable” human being —— from body to mind, from mood to moral capacity —— is embedded in particular cultural understandings. To be sure, some of those understandings are dynamic not static. For example, different human conditions can be “medicalized,” that is, transformed into treatable disorders, treatable within the purview of a particular system of health care and thus justified within it. A different form of dynamic framing within health care: the libertarian or neoliberal notion that whatever a physician and a patient can negotiate between themselves as medical treatment viable for them, even if rejected by others, as elective enhancement, not medically indicated therapy.
Both forms of dynamic framing within health care offer analogies for dynamic framings of genetic enhancement. I envision a different form of dynamism, that of a continually developing, principled path of thoughtful, rational deliberation toward framing an evolving, consensually held understanding of the proper domain of the practice of genetic engineering and genetic therapy (the hard part). Consensually held understandings would replace particular conventions that can provide no better justification than convention for how best to understand biomedical developments and possible practices. Consensually held understandings would also expand the critical examination of professional practices from internal to both internal and external.
The idea of humankind directing, politically, the course of its own evolution does not necessarily mean taking control of the species’ genome. It could mean taking control of the socially constructed cultural environment in which genetic enhancement takes places. That is, the human gene pool is not well conceived as a non-renewable natural resource vulnerable to exploitation, pollution, purification, diversion, or exhaustion. Perhaps the best way to approach the political challenge of genetic engineering is to focus on the perennial political tasks of maintaining, developing, and protecting mutual respect, good will, and tolerance for some kinds of difference, and beyond that, political communities of justice. The intractable question -- is there a human nature and, if so, what it might be? -- is then the question of what constitutes human well-being, just social arrangements, as well as individual and collective virtue. It is, in short, the question: not, What is our nature? But rather: What do we humans (beginning with those privileged to be part of the debate), as we aspire to just communities (conceived in a variety of ways), want our nature(s) to be?
WORK PLAN
I plan two weeks researching, writing, and discussion toward a first draft of each of three dimensions of the political challenge of genetic engineering. That is, human nature as cultural design weakens the nature/culture distinction (chapter 1), renders genetic engineering a specifically political act (chapter 2), and calls for new thinking on legal regulation, within and across national boundaries (chapter 3)?
Chapter 1, key questions: To what extent might genetic engineering emancipate humanity from some of its evolved characteristics? To what extent might the modifiers in effect rob genetically modified persons of individual autonomy, personal freedom, and moral equality with others? How might genetic engineering further human reason, individual autonomy, and democratic deliberation —— if at all? To answer that question, must a political community commit to a possibly problematic individualism, or to a conception of traits worthy of preservation, if not enhancement?
Chapter 2, key questions: How must social and political environments change, how must they be re-configured, for political communities where genetic engineering becomes part of a process toward the political self-realization of the individual? Is genetic chance —— freedom from genetic manipulation —— a psychologically, culturally or legally necessary precondition for contemporary liberal conceptions of individual freedom? Or, on the contrary, is genetic choice —— freedom to engineer —— a possible spring of individual freedom? These are not questions of natural science; they could be moral questions; I pose them as political questions.
Chapter 3, key questions: Can the social construction of social norms not only respond to biotechnological developments but in some way also guide them? In a liberal democratic society, can public debate and other forms of citizen participation contribute to the formulation of regulation in the way issues are framed normatively and resoled legally? What general principles might direct the regulation of genetic engineering: Principles such as freedom from engineering where engineering might undermine individual freedom, and freedom to enhance where enhancement might facilitate social, political, and legal freedom?
Seminar Planned in Shanghai and Hong Kong 2017
University of Texas at Austin Summer Session 2017 Fudan University, Shanghai
SEMINAR-IN-PLANNING
US-CHINA RELATIONS IN SHANGHAI & HONG KONG <syllabus-in-progress>
Professor Benjamin Gregg
GOV 360N
No country will figure more prominently in America’s future than China; the American-Chinese relationship has become the single most important bilateral relationship in the world today. Now the world’s second largest economy, and growing, China has emerged as a great military and political power and geopolitical rival to the USA. Not surprisingly, China’s rapid rise has generated considerable debate in the United States over how best to respond. Should Washington seek to contain Chinese power or, alternatively, concede that China has already become the world’s other superpower? At the heart of this debate are conflicting judgments about China’s intentions and capabilities as well as about America’s goals and actual power. The current debate is similar to the Cold War debates about how Washington should deal with China. In the early 1950s, Washington sought to contain and isolate China. In the 1970s, it reversed course and looked for ways to strengthen its ties. Many of the choices and trade-offs that Washington weighed in the past are again in play. The seminar closely examines some of those choices.
It focuses on some of the key sources of American foreign policy toward China, just as it considers how Chinese leaders view the United States. It explores issues of particular concern to both governments today (particularly Taiwan, Japan, North Korea, and the South China Sea). To place Western engagement with China in historical perspective, the seminar begins with the Opium Wars of the nineteenth century. To explore the possibility that there is more than one model for China’s future, students spend a week in Hong Kong, with three lectures by Hong Kong scholars whose analyses differ from those of the Chinese government and the three lectures by Shanghai scholars. Comparisons between the authoritarian government in Beijing and the surprising degree of political liberalism in Hong Kong allow for a more nuanced approach to possible trajectories of Chinese politics, and of US-China relations, in the twenty-first century.
Further, field trips in Shanghai and Hong Kong offer students a quotidian, street-level appreciation of some of the changes afoot in contemporary China along economic, political, and social dimensions. We visit the American Consulate in Shanghai for discussions about the American government’s mission in China as well as for information on a possible career in the diplomatic core (several members of the Consulate are alumni).
Finally, in both Shanghai and Hong Kong students may use their free time to make private day-trips via train (e.g., from Shanghai to Hangzhou and/or Suzhou, or to Beijing; and from Hong Kong to Macau and/or Shenzhen).
At our Shanghai base, supplementary classes on Chinese history and society, as well as on basic aspects of the Chinese language, enhance students’ overall understanding.
REQUIRED READINGS:
Orville Schell and John Delury, Wealth and Power: China’s Long March to the Twenty-First Century (Random House 2014)
Susan Shirk, The Fragile Superpower (Oxford 2007)
David Shambaugh, China Goes Global: The Partial Power (Oxford 2014)
Hugh White, The China Choice: Why We Should Share Power (Oxford 2013)
The following readings are available on our seminar’s Canvas site:
Robert Art (2010), “The United States and the Rise of China: Implications for the Long Haul,” Political Science Quarterly 125:359-391
Kenneth Lieberthal and Wang Jisi (2012), “Addressing U.S.-China Strategic Distrust,” Thornton China Center at Brookings
Emilian Kavalski (2014) “Chinese Normative Communities of Practice: Comparative Study of China’s Relational Governance of Africa and Central Asia,” in Xing, Li, and Farah, Abdulkadir Osman, eds. International Political Economy of New Regionalisms Series: China-Africa Relations in an Era of Great Transformation. Farnham, UK: Ashgate
Chen Wenjie, David Dollar and Heiwai Tang (2015), “How Similar is Chinese Investment in Africa to the West’s”? The Brookings Institution. August 18
EVALUATION: Students must complete all readings listed on the syllabus, attend all course sessions without exception, and participate in all field trips. A student’s final grade will be the average of three essays, each five to six double-spaced pages, adjusted for quality of class participation. All essays must be submitted via Canvas upload, on time. Due dates to be announced during the first week of seminar.
QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS FOR STUDENTS AND THEIR PARENTS
What academic needs does this program meet?
This seminar offers itself to any student interested in international relations, comparative politics, globalization, and/or China in particular. It meets the needs of students interested in the single most important bilateral relationship in the world today; it exposes them to one of the world’s major powers, cultures, economies, and its long history and centuries-old engagement with the West.
How does this seminar fit Departmental and University goals of exposing students to international experiences?
The College and Department stress the importance of students’ understanding of major contemporary globalizing phenomenon, among which China’s development into a world economic, military, and political power are prominent. These factors render the US-China relationship the single most important bilateral relationship in the world today. Our seminar demonstrates the relationship between globalization and geopolitics; investigates the dramatic change within China since 1978; and analyzes the emerging rivalry between China and the USA on multiple fronts, including the robust competition between the “Washington Consensus” and the “Beijing Consensus” with regard to models of development in the Third World in the twenty-first century.
Why China? Why Shanghai and Hong Kong in particular?
1. GEOPOLITICAL RIVALY BETWEEN USA AND CHINA: The seminar examines the recent development of China into world’s second largest economy (and growing), and now into a political super-power with strategic interests in Asia and Africa that compete directly with American interests. The overseas program exposes students to two very different sets of local Chinese perspectives on a range of key issues. These perspectives are not readily available in the USA in the way in which they are available on site, where students can question their interlocutors face-to-face, in real time. I refer to perspectives of the Chinese government, which we examine in Shanghai, and alternative indigenous perspectives, which we study in Hong Kong. Core learning goals include the student’s mastery of basic information; his or her critical thinking on international relations, developing a basic familiarity with China; acquiring a foundation in a crucial area of American foreign policy; and gaining an in-depth understanding of the most significant geopolitical issue of the twenty-first century. That issue is the heart of this seminar: the rivalry between the USA and China along economic, political, and social dimensions. This rivalry plays itself out between the two countries but in many other regions of the world as well (our course examines that rivalry in East Asia and in Africa, in particular).
2. DOMESTIC RIVALY BETWEEN MAINLAND AND HONG KONG: The terms on which Hong Kong returned to China allowed for limited, yet very real, democratization along with the continuation of social and economic legacies of the British colonial period. At the heart of the disputes over Hong Kong’s future: Can it be truly self-determining in a democratic sense or must it become just one more region within an authoritarian system? Hong Kong’s relationship to the mainland is related in some ways to Taiwan’s. In both communities, students observe a non-authoritarian Chinese alternative to the dictatorship held by the Chinese Communist Party since 1949. Beginning in 1978, the mainland has followed Hong Kong and Taiwan in integrating itself into the world market system. That integration inevitably poses major political questions to the Beijing leadership, including questions of both domestic and foreign policy. With regard to domestic policy: In what ways, and to what extent, does a capitalist system generate tensions within an authoritarian political system? With regard to foreign policy: the Taiwanese leadership views Beijing’s treatment of Hong Kong as a test case for how Beijing might treat Taiwan in the future. The USA has treaty obligations to defend Taiwan in case of attack; a mainland attack on Taiwan (to reunify it with the mainland), perhaps in response to a unilateral declaration of independence by Taiwan, would trigger American military involvement. Students will study these strategic interrelationships – directly relevant to America’s relations with China – on site, with local scholars (and, in the case of Hong Kong, scholars not beholden to Beijing).
3. SHANGHAI is China’s most populous city, with more than 24 million inhabitants; the global financial center of the world’s second largest economy; became historically significant when Europeans, Americans, and Japanese developed it into the financial hub of the Asia Pacific, a status it have achieved again since 1990s. As the most internationalized of any of China’s regions, Shanghai is more representative of China’s future relations with the USA than any other part of the country. No other Chinese venue is as well suited for American students to examine both the long history of American engagement in China and models for new forms of engagement in the new century.
4. HONG KONG, one of two Special Administrative Regions, has more than 7 million inhabitants within only 426 square miles, making it one of the world’s most densely populated cities. The British empire established is as a colony in the 1840s and ruled it until 1997. Today it is the world’s third most important financial center. It does not share the mainland’s political system and its independent judiciary inherited Britain’s common law framework. It enjoys a meaningful level of autonomy vis-à-vis the mainland (expect in defense and in foreign relations). It is weakly democratic, with a low level of political rights, but is nonetheless liberal in comparison to the mainland. Our visit offers students a passel of thought-provoking contrasts: one of the highest per capita incomes in the world, with a high Human Development Index, yet the largest income inequality among advanced economies. Given its unique political and social systems, Hong Kong relates to the West, and to the USA in particular, differently than does Shanghai and the mainland more generally. Hong Kong demonstrates some of the ways in which Chinese politics is not monolithic but rather contains competing visions of political and social organization, and for US-China relations, for the coming decades.
Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, Oxford 2017-18
Position: Visiting Scholar
Research Project: The Political, Legal, and Moral Consequences of the Human Species Taking Control of its Genome
More information to come
Masterclass on New Book 2015 Glasgow
Masterclass with Professor Benjamin Gregg on
“The Human Rights State”
20th May 2015, 10 am – 1.30 pm, Seminar Room at the Gilchrist Postgraduate Club, Gilbert Scott Building,
University Avenue, University of Glasgow, Scotland
Program:
10.00: Introduction of participants, chair: Dr Carole Baillie;
The Human Rights State: A Project for the Free Embrace of Human Rights
Author’s introduction to the book by Prof Benjamin Gregg.
10.20: Paper presentations and discussion of Section 1,
The Human Rights State: Politics through Metaphor
Chapter 1. Human Rights as Metaphor
Chapter 2. Human Rights in a Backpack
Chapter 3. The Body as Human Rights Boundary
Presentations by Anita Horn & René Wolfsteller.
11.05: Paper presentations and discussion of Section 2,
The Human Rights State through Persuasion
Chapter 4. Teaching Human Rights as a Cognitive Style
Chapter 5. Developing Human Rights Commitment in Post-Authoritarian Societies
Chapter 6. Digital Technology as Resource for the Human Rights Project
Presentations by Dr Claire Cassidy & Richard Georgi.
11.50: Coffee break
12.00: Paper presentations and discussion of Section 3,
Defense of the Human Rights State in the Face of Challenges
Chapter 7. Human Rights Patriotism
Chapter 8. A Human Right not to Democracy but to the Rule of Law
Chapter 9. Human Rights and Humanitarian Intervention
Presentations by Dr Awol Allo & Johannes Fahner.
12.45: Concluding discussion of the book,
Coda: A Community of Nation States Practicing Domestic Cosmopolitanism
Paper presentation by Ulisses Terto Neto.
13.30: The End.
Participants:
Presenters
Prof. Benjamin Gregg (UT at Austin)
Anita Horn (University of Zürich/St. Gallen)
René Wolfsteller (University of Glasgow)
Dr Claire Cassidy (University of Strathclyde)
Richard Georgi
Dr Awol Allo (London School of Economics)
Johannes Fahner (University of Luxembourg)
Ulisses Terto Neto (University of Aberdeen)
Discussants:
Dr Carole Baillie, chair (University of Glasgow)
Bethia Pearson (University of Glasgow)
Dr Matthew Waites (University of Glasgow)
Zuleykha Mailzada (University of Glasgow)
Yingru Li (University of Glasgow)
Gayatri Patel (Aston University)
Basak Baglayan (University of Luxembourg)
Book 2018 ::: Human Nature as Cultural Design
in preparation
HUMAN NATURE as CULTURAL DESIGN
The Political Challenge of Genetic Enhancement
Benjamin Gregg
.
Work-in-progress, accepted for review at CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
.
For the first time since evolving 200,000 years ago, Homo sapiens sapiens may soon transform itself biologically, a development no less significant than Copernicus’ transformation of the geocentric world view or Darwin’s of the anthropocentric understanding of animal life. One aspect of transformation is irresistibly hopeful: making predictive genetics available to all persons so that all might avoid or minimize genetic risks; providing prenatal genetic modification to decrease disease-susceptibility, eradicate congenital disabilities and extend life-span. But a different aspect of transformation unnerves: like the Copernican and Darwinian revolutions, it forces us to re-evaluate our understandings of ourselves as human beings and our relationship to other forms of life on our planet.
Consider, for example, the prospect of genetically engineering human intelligence. And of the many questions that pose themselves, consider two.
First, is it ethical? The answer to this question depends on the ethics one invokes in answering it. Any answer is likely to involve one or the other of the many conceptions of human nature.
If “human nature” is something natural, such as an aspect of a wholly naturalistic understanding of the evolved species homo sapiens, then engineering any part of it, including human intelligence, is not unethical from the standpoint of natural science because natural science has no moral content, indeed no meaning whatsoever.
But over the last ten thousand years, thisworldly nature has been interpreted non-scientifically again and again, for example from the otherworldly perspectives of religion and metaphysics. These perspectives invest nature with distinctly non-natural properties. The Book of Genesis, written in the 6th or 5th century BCE, invests the natural universe with divine design and purpose. From that perspective, engineering the human being may be regarded as violating a sacred design (but presumably only for those who share this very particular worldview).
Modern biology has no concept of what philosophers, theologians, and poets call “human nature.” Still, modern secular political communities, such as liberal democratic nation states, need to socially construct a range of human natures for purposes of social organization. Above all, one or the other notion of human nature can be useful in grounding the normative legitimation of a system of laws and to guide some forms of public policy.
For example, the German Constitution, Article 1, declares that “human dignity shall be inviolable.” The term dignity may be interpreted as allowing the engineering of human intelligence; it can just as well be interpreted as not allowing it. Either interpretation will base itself on a particular conception of human nature. That conception will be law not because it is true — propositions about nature can be true or false (as a matter of objectivity) whereas propositions about how people should be treated can be just or unjust (as a matter of intersubjective social construction).
In sum, whether it is ethical to engineer human intelligence depends on what ethical system one deploys to answer this question. There are many ethical systems in history, in the world today, and new ones no doubt will be developed in the future. All of these are incompatible with each other to various degrees, and agreement on any one is in principle possible, but exceedingly unlikely today. The basis of such agreement would be a political act of a global embrace of a particular cultural understanding, for example like the widespread conviction today that slavery is unacceptable on any grounds.
A second question about prospect of genetically engineering human intelligence concerns desirability. Again, any answer to this question depends on one’s particular point of view ( there are no “objective” or “neutral” standpoints here). From whom might it be desirable or undesirable? For the individual? For his or her community? For humankind? For the planet? In each case, both yes and no are plausible answers. For intelligence in any environment is double-edged: it has no inherent moral compass and can facilitate just behavior as well as unjust, decency no less than barbarism.
Consider the individual: greater intelligence means heightened capacity to imagine and realize goals — but could just as well damn the recipient to the continual frustration of a world that will not bend to his or her will. Consider the community: heightened intelligence promises a more productive, creative, and thoughtful populace — but could also result in more aggressive, selfish persons better able than unenhanced citizens to take advantage of fellow citizens. Consider humankind: might a species of greater intelligence better find its way to a peaceful world of just communities — or to an intellectual, social, and material “arms race” among competing groups? Consider the planet: would a species of higher intelligence be a better steward of the fragile planet it shares with other species — or one more rapacious, because its heightened intelligence unleashed heightened needs and the will to realize them even at the planet’s expense?
This exercise merely shows the obvious: that the knife that can save a life can also take a life. Less obvious because necessarily hypothetical are unintended consequences. The very fact of their not being intended marks such consequences as risks. Some risks follow simply from the powerful, exceeding complex interdependencies of various variables. While some risks pay off, others don’t. Is heightened intelligence worth that risk? We cannot yet know.
Further, engineering costs money and, at least initially, only wealthy persons would be able to afford the enhancement. In this way, engineered intelligence would exacerbate existing social and economic disparities if, as seems likely, greater intelligence confers advantages in the various spheres of life in which people compete for advantage — spheres in which some are perpetual losers.
In short, whether it is ethical and desirable to engineer higher intelligence depends not on the heightened intelligence as such but on the complex weave of social, political, economic, cultural and ecological factors that compose human communities. These factors constitute the environment in which bearers of engineered higher intelligence behave. Consider just two factors: wealth and influence. Money is power and people struggle mightily against each other to gain more wealth and wield greater influence, both as individuals and as groups and as nation states. If, as seems likely, heightened intelligence confers advantages, at least to some recipients, at least some of the time, at least in some circumstances, one can imagine a socially destabilizing struggle to control access to it—a struggle with winners, losers, and “collateral damage.” But not necessarily.
I am currently writing a book titled << Human Nature as Cultural Design: The Political Challenge of Human Genetic Engineering >>. I argue that any estimation of the problems and prospects of human intelligence, whether engineered or not, will depend on some conception of human nature. If human nature is, as I argue, a social construction, the two questions I consider above will find quite a range of answers in a context of deep, intractable, and abiding disagreement both within communities and cultures as well as across different ones. Clearly the questions need creative thinking and analysis — and legislation on regulation —beyond anything any community or any belief system has yet produced.
I seek to answer these and many other questions in terms of a new, comprehensive political theory. I am guided by the following conviction. The idea of humankind directing, politically, the course of its own evolution does not necessarily mean taking control of the species’ genome. It could mean taking control of the socially constructed cultural environment in which genetic enhancement takes places. That is, the human gene pool is not well conceived as a non-renewable natural resource vulnerable to exploitation, pollution, purification, diversion, or exhaustion. And it cannot be preserved like a jar of raspberry jam: it has no edges, neither floor nor ceiling. Perhaps the best way to approach the specifically political challenge of genetic engineering is to focus on the perennial political tasks of maintaining, developing, and protecting mutual respect, good will, and tolerance for some kinds of difference, and beyond that, political communities of justice. The moral and political question — is there some kind of human nature and, if so, what it might be? — is then the question of what constitutes human well-being, just social arrangements, as well as individual and collective virtue. It is, in short, the question: not, What is our nature? But rather: What do we want our nature to be? What do we humans (beginning with those privileged to be part of the debate), as we aspire to just communities (conceived in a variety of ways), aspire to morally and what resources and dangers might human genetic engineering contain?
I imagine a new kind of normative thinking in place of the current normative impasse in thinking, where no particular understanding of the proper goals and functions of genetic engineering can provide guidance beyond this or that sliver of cultural preference.
Ethical to Genetically Engineer Intelligence?
http://www.hopesandfears.com/hopes/now/question/215463-is-it-ethical-to-genetically-engineer-higher-intelligence
Fulbright Professorship 2016 Austria
Johannes-Kepler-Universität Linz ▪ Sommermester 2016
IDEOLOGIETHEORIEN
Blockveranstaltung im Mastercurriculum ▪ in deutscher Sprache
März, April, Juni ▪ Freitags
LVA 229.203 ▪ ECTS 3,0 ▪ SSt. 2,0
Fr ▪ 11.03.2016 9:15-11:45 & 12:45 bis 18:00 (mit Pausen) BA 9909 / MZ 412A
Fr ▪ 08.04.2016 12:45 bis 18:00 (mit Pausen) MZ 412A
Fr ▪ 22.04.2016 9:15-11:45 & 12:45 bis 18:00 (mit Pausen) K269D / MZ 412A
Fr ▪ 03.06.2016 12:45 bis 18:00 (mit Pausen) MZ 412A
Prof. Dr. Benjamin Gregg
▪ Fulbright–Johannes-Kepler-Universität Linz Gastprofessor ▪
University of Texas, Department of Government, 1 University Station A-1800
Austin, Texas 78712 USA
KOMMENTAR ▪Ziel der Veranstaltung ist es, das Phänomen der Ideologie differenziert zu beleuchten. Wir untersuchen sechs der einflußreichsten Ideologietheorien im Hinblick auf ihr Leistungspotential, die komplexe, moderne westliche Gesellschaft kritisch zu analysieren. Unsere sechs Theorien unterscheiden sich in vielerlei Hinsicht von einander alle aber befassen sich mit den praktischen Entstehungsbedingungen und Konsequenzen von Ideologien in einer Gesellschft; mit dem Einfluß gesellschaftlicher Faktoren auf die Entstehung, Verbreitung und Verkehrung von Ideologien; und mit der Implikation von sozialen Faktoren in Ideensystemen, die mit dem Anspurch auf Geltung, Wahrheit und Verbindlichkeit auftreten. Das Seminar ist als Einführung konzipiert und setzt keine Vorkenntnisse voraus.
LITERATUR ▪
Sigmund Freud: Das Unbehagen in der Kultur ▪ Reclam ISBN 978-3-15-018697-8
G.W.F. Hegel: Einleitung zur Phänomenologie des Geistes ▪ Reclam ISBN 978-3-15-008461-8
Max Weber: Wissenschaft als Beruf ▪ Reclam ISBN 978-3-15-009388-7
Max Horkheimer / Theodor W. Adorno: Kulturindustrie: Aufklärung als Massenbetrug ▪ Reclam ISBN 978-3-15-019273-3
Karl Marx: Ökonomische und philosophische Schriften ▪ Reclam ISBN 978-3-15-018554-4
Friedrich Nietzsche: Zur Genealogie der Moral ▪ Reclam ISBN 978-3-15-007123-6
HINWEIS ZUR VERANSTALTUNG ▪Verpflichtend ist die Teilnahme an allen vier Seminartagen.
LEISTUNGSNACHWEIS ▪Für einen benoteten Schein: ein textanalytischer Aufsatz von 6 bis 8 Seiten in deutscher oder englischer Sprache, der eine bestimmte Fragestellung zu einem oder mehreren unseren Autoren kritisch und eingehend diskutiert. Abgabetermin ist der 18. August 2016 per elektronische Zusendung (Email-Anhang in Word).
▪ SEMINARPLAN ▪
Pflichtlektüre: bitte vor dem jeweiligen Blocktermin lesen
11. März ▪ Nietzsche, Zur Genealogie der Moral (1887), Erste Abhandlung, “Gut und Böse, Gut und Schlecht”, Seiten 13-44
▪ undFreud, Das Unbehagen in der Kultur (1930), Kapitel 2, 3, 7, 8 (Seiten 18-46, 74-100)
08. April ▪ Weber, Wissenschaft als Beruf (1919), Seiten 3-45
22. April ▪ Marx, Ökonomische und philosophische Schriften (1844), “Die entfremdete Arbeit”, Seiten 28-45
▪ und Horkheimer/Adorno, Kulturindustrie: Aufklärung als Massenbetrug (1944), Seiten 7-23, 41-48, 65-73
03. Juni ▪ Hegel, Einleitung zur Phänomenologie des Geistes (1807), Seiten 7-19; siehe dazu die Kommentare zu diesen Seiten im Exemplar im Handapparat der Institutsbibliothek
Symposium on New Book 2016 Sweden
http://www.jur.lu.se/#!ID0DEF29E16A3AB50FC1257F6C003A912F
Seminar with Professor Benjamin Gregg, University of Texas 2016-03-04
Forskning Seminar April 6 at 10-12 in Styrelserummet, Juridicum.
We are delighted to invite you to an informal seminar with Professor Benjamin Gregg, Department of Government, University of Texas at Austin and currently Fulbright Guest Professor at the University of Linz, Austria.
Date and time: 6 April, 10-12 Venue: Styrelserummet, 4th floor, Faculty of Law, Lund University, Lilla Gråbrödersgatan 4. (http://www.jur.lu.se/#!hittatillJuridicum)
The focus of the seminar is Benjamin Gregg’s forthcoming book: The Human Rights State:Justice Within and Beyond Sovereign Nations, part of the Pennsylvania Studies in Human Rights series. (By coincidence, the official date of publication is April 6.)
Benjamin Gregg will start the seminar with an introduction and would then be very pleased to engage interested participants in spontaneous conversation during the seminar about any aspect of the book. Participants who wish are invited to submit brief questions, observations, critiques, or suggestions to Teresa.Oneill@jur.lu.se by March 30. Please note that no one need prepare in advance any kind of engagement with the text to enjoy a warm welcome as a seminar participant.
As Benjamin Gregg’s work straddles many disciplines, we see this as an opportunity to meet and engage in conversation across institutional and disciplinary borders and we hope to see you there!
Abstract: The nation state operates on a logic of exclusion: no state can offer citizenship and legal rights to all comers. From the logic of exclusion a state derives its sovereign power. Yet this exclusivity undermines the project of advancing human rights globally. That project operates on a logic of inclusion: all people, regardless of citizenship status or territorial location, would everywhere be recognized as bearers of human rights. In practice, human rights are afforded, if at all, then only to citizens of those few states that sometimes regard human rights as moral necessities of domestic commitments—or for states that find that stance politically expedient for the moment. This discouraging reality in the first decades of the twenty-first century prompts the question: What political arrangement might better conduce the local embrace and enduring practice of human rights? In The Human Rights State, Benjamin Gregg challenges the conviction that the nation state can only have a zero-sum relationship with human rights: national sovereignty is possible or human rights are possible, but not both, not in the same place, at the same time. He argues that the human rights project would be more effective if established and enforced at local levels as locally valid norms, and from there encouraged to expand outward toward overlaps with other locally established and enforced conceptions of human rights grown in their own local soils. Proposing a metaphorical human rights state that operates within or alongside a nation state, Gregg describes networks of activists that encourage local political and legal systems to generate domestic obligations to enforce human rights. Geographic boundaries and national sovereignties would remain intact but diminished to the extent necessary to extend human rights to all persons, without reservation, across national borders, by rendering human rights an integral aspect of the nation state's constitution.
You can find out more about the work of Benjamin Gregg here:http://www.utexas.edu/cola/government/faculty/bggregg
To receive the manuscript of the book write to Teresa.Oneill@jur.lu.se.
Anna Bruce, Researcher, Faculty of Law
Lena Halldenius, Professor of Human Rights, Human Rights Studies
Martha F. Davis, 2015-2016 Fulbright Distinguished Chair of Human Rights and Humanitarian Law at the Raoul Wallenberg Institute of Human Rights and Humanitarian Law
International Seminar 2016 Japan
INTERNATIONAL SEMINAR
Law and Politics of Human Rights in Global Culture
(with special reference to Japan)
School of Law
University of Hokkaido
Sapporo, Japan
August 2016
http://hokkaidosummerinstitute.oia.hokudai.ac.jp/courses/u09.html
FACULTY:
Prof. Benjamin Gregg, University of Texas at Austin, Department of Government
Prof. Ko Hasegawa, Hokkaido University, School of Law
Prof. Yasuo Tsuji, Hokkaido University, School of Public Policy
Prof. Ken’ichi Ochiai, Hokkaido University, Center for Ainu and Indigenous Studies
SEMINAR DESCRIPTION: Today we have the web of various rights protections in our legal and political systems, national and international. This web has been shaped in the course of historical development since the late 18th century, especially after the end of WWII. Based on the modern development of the protection of individual rights in various national constitutions, the web of human rights protections in international context has been much extended until today. This great movement in human history and civilization is now facing with divergent new problem situations such as the ICT revolution, environmental crisis, population migration or genetic engineerings. How and to what extent can the framework of the protection of human rights be effective for coping not only with traditional problems of the protection of human freedom and equality but also with the novel problems on global scale today? In this course, we will try to understand the normative potentials of the idea of human rights in law and politics for these urgent tasks for all of us.
SEMINAR GOALS:
Week 1: 1) the basic features of the concept of human rights as well it social functions; 2) the legal and political grounds of the concept of human rights; and 3) the variety of human rights protections.
Week 2: 1) the cultural resource of human rights ideas in divergent societies; 2) global and local aspects of human rights workings; and 3) the significance of our cognitive framing in human rights thinking.
Week 3: 1) various aspects of the social realization of human rights ideas; 2) human rights in the midst of the reality of political systems; and 3) the future possibilities of human rights perspectives.
SCHEDULE OF TOPICS:
Mon, Aug 8: Introduction: the World of Law and Politics in Global Context
Tues, Aug 9: The Basis of the Idea of Rights
Wed, Aug 10: The Salient Features of the Idea of Rights
Thu, Aug 11: The Significance of Human Rights
Fri, Aug 12: Varieties of Human Rights
Mon, Aug 15: Generating Universal Human Rights out of Local Norms
Tues, Aug 16: Cultural Resources: Individuals as Authors of Human Rights
Wed, Aug 17: Emotions and Natural Altruism in Support of Human Rights
Thu, Aug 18: Translating Human Rights into Local Cultural Vernaculars
Fri, Aug 19: Advancing Human Rights through Cognitive Reframing
Mon, Aug 22: Teaching Human Rights as a Cognitive Style
Tues, Aug 23: Developing Human Rights Commitment in Post-Authoritarian Societies
Wed, Aug 24: Reconciling Human Rights and the Sovereign State: Patriotism
Thu, Aug 25: A Human Right not to Democracy but to the Rule of Law
Fri, Aug 26: Human Rights and Humanitarian Intervention
HOKKAIDO SUMMER INSTITUTE ::: Kita 15, Nishi 8, Kita-ku, Sapporo Hokkaido 060-0815
Lecture, Raoul Wallenberg Institute, Sweden 2016
http://rwi.lu.se/2016/03/the-human-rights-challenge-of-genetic-engineering/
The Human Rights Challenge of Genetic Engineering
What would the impact be on human rights if the genetic variants associated with IQ are discovered?
That is the question Dr. Benjamin Gregg will be discussing when he visits the Raoul Wallenberg Institute on 6 April.
In a public lecture in co-operation with the Department of Biology at Lund University. The lecture is supported by the Fulbright Scholar Program.
Dr. Benjamin Gregg is a professor of social and political theory at the University of Texas. He is the Fulbright Visiting Professor at Johannes Kepler University of Linz, Austria. His current research focus is human rights and genomic manipulation.
Gregg says rapid developments in genetics and associated technology raise difficult social, moral, economic and political questions about what should be allowed and what might best be prohibited.
“I approach this issue in terms of one particular example of great and enduring significance to individuals, groups, whole societies, and the world community,” he says. “If the genetic variants associated with different levels of IQ are discovered, what kind of human rights thinking might be deployed to answer such questions as: On the basis of preimplantation genetic diagnosis, should parents be allowed to select the embryo with variants associated even with a very slightly higher IQ and discard an embryo with an average IQ? Should we distinguish between raising, to average, the IQ of a baby (by manipulating the embryo) with an IQ significantly below average, and raising a normal IQ to a level much above average?”
As a political theorist Gregg develops a normative framework in terms of which questions can be evaluated and addressed from a human rights standpoint.
Time: Wednesday 6 April at 16:30-17:30
Location: Beijing conference room, Raoul Wallenberg Institute, Stora Gråbrödersgatan 17
For more information, please contact
University of Helsinki, Finland 2016
The Erik Castrén Institute of International Law and Human Rights, University of Helsinki, Finland
24-25 May 2016
Guest Lectures
::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::
http://www.helsinki.fi/eci/Events/gregg1.html
Guest Lecture by Prof. Gregg on Human Rights and Genetic Engineering.
Date and Time: 24th May 14.00-16.00 in Porthania P518
Hosted by Prof. Jaana Hallamaa, from Theology Department.
Prof. Gregg will present proposals for how best to understand and advance human rights, in particular with respect to issues of human genetic engineering. This rapidly developing technology raises urgent and difficult human rights questions. Prof. Gregg’s work concerns translating, into the human rights vocabulary, cutting-edge research and fast-developing biotechnology focusing on human genetic engineering.
Prof. Gregg will deliver a public lecture on the human rights challenge of human genetic engineering. The lecture will be followed by discussion.
Bio: Benjamin Gregg, currently a Fulbright Research Professor at the University of Linz in Austira, teaches social and political theory at the University of Texas at Austin, and often in Germany (Frankfurt/Oder), Austria (Innsbruck and Linz), China (Tsinghua and Shanghai Jiao Tong), and Japan (Hokkaido). He graduated from Yale College with a degree in philosophy, received a D.Phil. from the Free University of Berlin in philosophy, and a Ph.D. from Princeton in political science (with an M.A. in sociology). Studied with Michael Walzer in Princeton, Axel Honneth in Berlin, and Seyla Benhabib at Yale. He is the author of Thick Moralities, Thin Politics (public policy suffers when politics are laden with moral doctrines; public policy should work not toward political consensus but toward the more realistic goal of mutual accommodation); Coping In Politics with Indeterminate Norms (while moral validity is relative rather than absolute, and cultural meanings local rather than universal, social integration and democratic politics are still attainable goals); and Human-Rights as Social Construction (human rights can be authored by the average, ordinary people to whom they are addressed, and that they are valid only if embraced by those to whom they would apply), and The Human Rights State (a metaphorical alternative to the nation state, a polity without territory, standing alongside the nation state, as a political and moral commitment that, in the pursuit of human rights, would limit the nation state without undermining it). He is currently working on a book for Cambridge University Press titled Human Nature as Cultural Design: The Political Challenge of Genetic Engineering (in the sense of genetic therapy and genetic “enhancement”).
::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::
http://www.helsinki.fi/eci/Events/gregg.html
Guest lecture by Benjamin Gregg on Human Rights via Fulbright Intercountry Travel Program
Time and Place: 25th May from 14:00-16:00 in Porthania P545, 5th floor.
Abstract: The nation state operates on a logic of exclusion: no state can offer citizenship and legal rights to all comers. From the logic of exclusion a state derives its sovereign power. Yet this exclusivity undermines the project of advancing human rights globally. That project operates on a logic of inclusion: all people, regardless of citizenship status or territorial location, would everywhere be recognized as bearers of human rights. In practice, human rights are afforded, if at all, then only to citizens of those few states that sometimes regard human rights as moral necessities of domestic commitments—or for states that find that stance politically expedient for the moment.
This discouraging reality in the first decades of the twenty-first century prompts the question: What political arrangement might better conduce the local embrace and enduring practice of human rights? In The Human Rights State, Benjamin Gregg challenges the conviction that the nation state can only have a zero-sum relationship with human rights: national sovereignty is possible or human rights are possible, but not both, not in the same place, at the same time. He argues that the human rights project would be more effective if established and enforced at local levels as locally valid norms, and from there encouraged to expand outward toward overlaps with other locally established and enforced conceptions of human rights grown in their own local soils.
Proposing a metaphorical human rights state that operates within or alongside a nation state, Gregg describes networks of activists that encourage local political and legal systems to generate domestic obligations to enforce human rights. Geographic boundaries and national sovereignties would remain intact but diminished to the extent necessary to extend human rights to all persons, without reservation, across national borders, by rendering human rights an integral aspect of the nation state's constitution.
Blog on Human Nature and Genetic Engineering 2016
http://pennpress.typepad.com/pennpresslog/2016/05/on-human-nature-and-genetically-engineered-human-intelligence.html
May 20, 2016
On Human Nature and Genetically Engineered Human Intelligence
Today we have a guest post from Benjamin Gregg, author of The Human Rights State: Justice Within and Beyond Sovereign Nations. Gregg's book challenges the conviction that the nation state can only have a zero-sum relationship with human rights: national sovereignty is possible or human rights are possible, but not both, not in the same place, at the same time. He argues that the human rights project would be more effective if established and enforced at local levels as locally valid norms, and from there encouraged to expand outward toward overlaps with other locally established and enforced conceptions of human rights grown in their own local soils. Proposing a metaphorical human rights state that operates within or alongside a nation state, Gregg describes networks of activists that encourage local political and legal systems to generate domestic obligations to enforce human rights.
For the first time since evolving 200,000 years ago, Homo sapiens sapiens may soon transform itself biologically, a development no less significant than Copernicus’ transformation of the geocentric world view or Darwin’s of the anthropocentric understanding of animal life. One aspect of transformation is irresistibly hopeful: making predictive genetics available to all persons so that all might avoid or minimize genetic risks; providing prenatal genetic modification to decrease disease-susceptibility, eradicate congenital disabilities and extend life-span. But a different aspect of transformation unnerves: like the Copernican and Darwinian revolutions, it forces us to re-evaluate our understandings of ourselves as human beings and our relationship to other forms of life on our planet. I do just that in a book I am currently writing titled Human Nature as Cultural Design: The Political Challenge of Human Genetic Engineering. For reasons I develop below, I argue that we humans should regard our own nature as socially constructed rather than as something given naturally or supernaturally.
Consider, for example, the prospect of genetically engineering human intelligence. And of the many questions that pose themselves, consider two.
First, is it ethical? The answer to this question depends on the ethics one invokes in answering it. Any answer is likely to involve one or the other of the many conceptions of human nature.
If “human nature” is something natural, such as an aspect of a wholly naturalistic understanding of the evolved species homo sapiens, then engineering any part of it, including human intelligence, is not unethical from the standpoint of natural science because natural science has no moral content, indeed no meaning whatsoever.
But over the last ten thousand years, this worldly nature has been interpreted non-scientifically again and again, for example from the otherworldly perspectives of religion and metaphysics. These perspectives invest nature with distinctly non-natural properties. The Book of Genesis, written in the 6th or 5th century BCE, invests the natural universe with divine design and purpose. From that perspective, engineering the human being may be regarded as violating a sacred design (but presumably only for those who share this very particular worldview).
Modern biology has no concept of what philosophers, theologians, and poets call “human nature.” Still, modern secular political communities, such as liberal democratic nation states, need to socially construct a range of human natures for purposes of social organization. Above all, one or the other notion of human nature can be useful in grounding the normative legitimation of a system of laws and to guide some forms of public policy.
For example, the German Constitution, Article 1, declares that “human dignity shall be inviolable.” The term dignity may be interpreted as allowing the engineering of human intelligence; it can just as well be interpreted as not allowing it. Either interpretation will base itself on a particular conception of human nature. That conception will be law not because it is true — propositions about nature can be true or false (as a matter of objectivity) whereas propositions about how people should be treated can be just or unjust (as a matter of intersubjective social construction).
In sum, whether it is ethical to engineer human intelligence depends on what ethical system one deploys to answer this question. There are many ethical systems in history, in the world today, and new ones no doubt will be developed in the future. All of these are incompatible with each other to various degrees, and agreement on any one is in principle possible, but exceedingly unlikely today. The basis of such agreement would be a political act of a global embrace of a particular cultural understanding, for example like the widespread conviction today that slavery is unacceptable on any grounds.
A second question about prospect of genetically engineering human intelligence concerns desirability. Again, any answer to this question depends on one’s particular point of view (there are no “objective” or “neutral” standpoints here). From whom might it be desirable or undesirable? For the individual? For his or her community? For humankind? For the planet? In each case, both yes and no are plausible answers. For intelligence in any environment is double-edged: it has no inherent moral compass and can facilitate just behavior as well as unjust, decency no less than barbarism.
Consider the individual: greater intelligence means heightened capacity to imagine and realize goals — but could just as well damn the recipient to the continual frustration of a world that will not bend to his or her will. Consider the community: heightened intelligence promises a more productive, creative, and thoughtful populace — but could also result in more aggressive, selfish persons better able than unenhanced citizens to take advantage of fellow citizens. Consider humankind: might a species of greater intelligence better find its way to a peaceful world of just communities — or to an intellectual, social, and material “arms race” among competing groups? Consider the planet: would a species of higher intelligence be a better steward of the fragile planet it shares with other species — or one more rapacious, because its heightened intelligence unleashed heightened needs and the will to realize them even at the planet’s expense?
This exercise merely shows the obvious: that the knife that can save a life can also take a life. Less obvious because necessarily hypothetical are unintended consequences. The very fact of their not being intended marks such consequences as risks. Some risks follow simply from the powerful, exceeding complex interdependencies of various variables. While some risks pay off, others don’t. Is heightened intelligence worth that risk? We cannot yet know.
Further, engineering costs money and, at least initially, only wealthy persons would be able to afford the enhancement. In this way, engineered intelligence would exacerbate existing social and economic disparities if, as seems likely, greater intelligence confers advantages in the various spheres of life in which people compete for advantage — spheres in which some are perpetual losers.
In short, whether it is ethical and desirable to engineer higher intelligence depends not on the heightened intelligence as such but on the complex weave of social, political, economic, cultural and ecological factors that compose human communities. These factors constitute the environment in which bearers of engineered higher intelligence behave. Consider just two factors: wealth and influence. Money is power and people struggle mightily against each other to gain more wealth and wield greater influence, both as individuals and as groups and as nation states. If, as seems likely, heightened intelligence confers advantages, at least to some recipients, at least some of the time, at least in some circumstances, one can imagine a socially destabilizing struggle to control access to it—a struggle with winners, losers, and “collateral damage.” But not necessarily.
Any estimation of the problems and prospects of human intelligence, whether engineered or not, will depend on some conception of human nature. If human nature is a social construction, the two questions I consider above will find quite a range of answers in a context of deep, intractable, and abiding disagreement within communities and across cultures. But I would hope to persuade my readers that the idea of humankind directing, politically, the course of its own evolution need not mean taking control of the species’ genome. It could mean taking control of the socially constructed cultural environment in which genetic enhancement takes places. The moral and political question — is there some kind of human nature and, if so, what it might be? — is then the question of what constitutes human well-being, just social arrangements, as well as individual and collective virtue. It is, in short, the question: not, What is our nature? But rather: What do we want our nature to be?
Review 1: Human Rights as Social Construction
Human Rights as Social Construction by Benjamin Gregg
Review 2 : Human Rights as Social Construction
René Wolfsteller
Human Rights Quarterly, Volume 36, Number 2, May 2014, pp. 492-496
(Article)
Published by The Johns Hopkins University Press
DOI: 10.1353/hrq.2014.0031
Benjamin Gregg, Human Rights as
Social Construction (Cambridge
University Press, 2013), ISBN 978-
1-1076-1294-5, 272 pages.
The evolution of the political theory of
human rights for the past twenty years
is perhaps best described—by altering
a phrase of Charles Taylor1—as a
“metaphysical limbo” of legitimation. In
the course of this “limbo” scholars from
various disciplines have been engaging in
a competition to provide a better, more
persuasive foundation for the universal
legitimacy of human rights, but simultaneously
with allegedly less demanding
1. Charles Taylor, What’s Wrong with Negative Liberty, in The Liberty Reader 162 (David
Miller ed., 2006).
2014 Book Reviews 493
assumptions. Yet, rather than revealing
a universal basis of legitimacy to make
human rights more accessible and attractive,
many scholarly suggestions
have contributed to the construction of
new boundaries. Those boundaries have
typically been the result of a dubious
recycling of rational inequality, whereby
some people are considered capable of
making use of their reason in a superior
way to others,2 and hence are able to
lead morally virtuous lives according to
human rights norms. For example, such
boundaries and limitations of equality
were fuelled by arguments that human
rights require a theological fundament,
like the belief in God and human sacredness.
3
In a more interventionist sense, the
liberal philosopher John Rawls argued
that societies abiding human rights as
“part of a reasonable law of peoples”
have the duty to subject so-called “outlaw
regimes” to the rule of “reasonable and
just law” in order to overcome the state of
nature.4 In his contribution to the debate,
the postmodernist Jean-François Lyotard
insisted on the fact that the “right to
speak” as “the most fundamental human
right” has to be merited by undergoing
a certain process of “civilization” to
free oneself from “his animal nature.”5
However, the nadir of this competition
has been the claim of the communitarian
Amitai Etzioni, whereby people “under
the influence of . . . alcohol, drugs, or
merely a high dose of mass culture, or
those who are mentally handicapped, are
blind to even the most shining normative
light,” and thus, are the main obstacle to
the realization of human rights within
liberal democratic societies.6
With his study Human Rights as Social
Construction, the political theorist
Benjamin Gregg intercedes in the dispute
with a conception of human rights that
tries to tear down those boundaries, to
make human rights more accessible,
and to mediate between the numerous
diverging approaches in the field. Gregg’s
aim is to ground the normative debate
over human rights in a “realistic” and
“pragmatic” way, and he does so mainly
by drawing on sociological and anthropological
insights. In fact, his book can
be considered the first analysis within the
field of political theory of human rights
that pays attention to sociological as well
as anthropological explanations to such
a serious extent. Backed up by this transdisciplinary
lens, Gregg puts a persistent
emphasis on the fact that particular local
communities of people always socially
construct moral norms.
Sociologists may find this assertion
to be a rather mundane insight. Within
normative political philosophy, however,
it allows Gregg to emphasize the
“political” nature of human rights as a
contingent “this-worldly” idea which is
up for negotiation, but not necessarily
ineffective or dispensable. Once we have
come to accept the fact that human beings
are the sole authors of social norms
on earth, it follows that it is both possible
and necessary to create effective
behavioral norms for themselves. From
that assumption Gregg deduces that
2. Cf. Niklas Luhmann, 2 Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft 1023 (1997).
3. Michael J. Perry, Toward a Theory of Human Rights: Religion, Law, Courts 25 (2007).
4. John Rawls, The Law of Peoples, in On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993,
at 41, 70–73 (Stephen Shute & Susan Hurley eds., 1993).
5. Jean-François Lyotard, The Other’s Rights, in On Human Rights, supra note 4, at 135,
141–42.
6. Amitai Etzioni, The Normativity of Human Rights Is Self-Evident, 32 Hum. Rts. Q. 194
(2010).
494 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Vol. 36
human rights are valid only if people
consciously and self-reflexively come to
hold human rights norms on an individual
level. Moreover, if these norms become
entrenched in the social institutions of
a community, such as the legal order
and public education, they will in turn
reinforce the development of individual
“human rights personalities.”7 Therefore,
he argues that people have to be socialized
into a solidarity based on the mutual
expectation of granting each other these
locally defined human rights. And yet, it
would not require a collective identity
or the idea of a human nature to bring
about a shared human rights consciousness,
because in a highly individuated
society it is much more promising that
people become integrated into a moral
community by “difference” rather than
by “identity.” Here, Gregg adopts Georg
Simmel’s observation that members of
modern societies are constantly weaving
themselves into multiple “webs of affiliations”
by interacting with different social
groups. Such “non-normative webs”
of group affiliations, Gregg concludes,
would help to raise awareness for the
interests and feelings of others precisely
as “others,” despite all their differences.8
After rejecting both theological9 and
metaphysical10 conceptions of human
rights, Gregg sets out in greater detail
how his approach might better contribute
to the core goal of the human rights
project which he sees as helping people
“at the bottom of social hierarchies,
and oppressed minorities and socially
marginalized groups” to get protection
from mistreatment by deploying “human
rights as a moral language to win for
themselves the human rights they want.”11
One essential element of his proposal is
the approach of “normative localism.”12
Inspired by the anthropological finding of
the cultural particularity of social norms,
Gregg develops the idea of deriving
normatively “thin” human rights from
“thick” local norms to reach an agreement
between different communities
that is more than just locally valid. Such
a minimalist understanding of human
rights norms would leave room for local
peculiarities and would not necessarily
require adopting a “Western” political
culture. If the most basic requirement
for human rights is the general capacity
to put oneself in the other’s shoes, then
Gregg sees potential for developing a
human rights consciousness in almost
any community. At the same time, a minimalist
understanding renders it a more
realistic goal to eventually reach universal
validity of human rights, namely when a
majority of communities freely embrace
them as moral norms on a local level.13
In order to accomplish this, Gregg also
explores how people can authorize and
grant themselves human rights in ways
that are not dependent on legal or political
institutions, although he admits that,
in the end, recognition by the state is desirable.
Since human rights are ultimately
a type of “belief system” which guide
people’s behavior, the key for Gregg is to
facilitate the development of a personality
structure of “assertive self-hood.” Such
a form of identity emerges through collective
political action, by challenging
oppressive authorities, and by adopting
7. Benjamin Gregg, Human Rights as Social Construction 25 (2013).
8. Id. at 51–54.
9. Id. at 13.
10. Id. at 37.
11. Id. at 33.
12. Id. at 57.
13. Id. at 62.
2014 Book Reviews 495
a non-idiosyncratic perspective that
“recognizes others in their self-granting
activity.”14 Ultimately, the difficult task
of the project for self-authored human
rights would be “to achieve recognition
even in local environments hostile to
them, and to do so from within the local
culture.”15 As one means to achieve
this recognition, Gregg investigates how
altruism as a natural emotional disposition
can be fostered through “sentimental
education”16 in order to supplement
rationally motivated practices of human
rights-based solidarity.17
Another direction suggested by Gregg
is to translate human rights into local,
culturally authentic vernaculars through
actors developing a “dual consciousness”
as rights-bearers on the one hand, and as
kinsmen on the other. Ideally then, indigenously
interpreted human rights would
resonate with local culture instead of
clashing with it.18 For human rights norms
to appear plausible and attractive enough
to be seized by local communities, Gregg
recommends a cognitive technique—reframing
the issues at stake—instead of
an attempt at persuasion by normative
argumentation.19
Following an excursion into problems
with defining the “human being” from a
constructivist point of view, in his final
chapter20 Gregg pleads for the substitution
of today’s nation-state with what he
calls the “human rights state.” According
to him, only a state, which recognizes
people’s rights and dignity, not according
to their arbitrary assignment to a nation
but to their status as biological members
of the human species, is likely to enforce
human rights effectively.21
This ambitious plea for the transformation
of the modern nation-state also indicates
that Gregg pursues a twofold goal.
On the one hand, his study is written in
the rigorously rationalistic and, at times,
quite lengthy style of analytic philosophy,
clearly aiming at an academic audience.
On the other hand, with its pragmatic
and realistic impetus, his exploration of
various resources to implement human
rights is certainly aspiring to have realworld
effects. Compared to the prevailing
approaches in the field, Gregg’s pool of
relatively concrete suggestions is indeed
closer to that aim than any other philosophical
conception of human rights.
Nevertheless, Gregg proves to be aware
of the limits of his argumentation, admitting
that “[t]he project for self-authored
human rights is inherently unlikely and
. . . will remain difficult to realize.”22 He
is also willing to acknowledge that, no
matter how normatively “thin” or minimal
human rights are being defined, as a set
of culturally specific norms they “cannot
be free of all cultural imperialism”23 and
will always pose a challenge for some
local communities if they are supposed
to have any effect. All the more important
for Gregg is to frame human rights norms
in a way that resonates with local culture.
However, the three strengths of
Gregg’s approach—realism, pragmatism,
14. Id. at 99.
15. See id. at 97; id. at 96.
16. Id. at 125.
17. Id. at 111.
18. Id. at 135.
19. Id. at 157.
20. Id. at 185.
21. Id. at 212.
22. Id. at 105.
23. Id. at 152.
496 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Vol. 36
and inter-disciplinarity—also give cause
for dissent. Gregg is not always successful
when he draws on concepts that were
grown within the intellectual habitat of
sociology or anthropology and attempts
to translate these into normative philosophical
currency. For instance, when
he develops the technique of “cognitive
reframing” by drawing on Erving
Goffman, it remains sketchy as to what
kind of additional benefit there is to be
illuminated, other than the (previously
stressed) insight on how important it is
for people to become socialized into a
belief system of human rights in the first
place. Moreover, there is an inherent
contradiction arising from Gregg’s human
rights conception with respect to its pragmatic
focus. Although he wants human
rights to be understood in a minimalist
fashion, that is, as a contingent “rhetorical
vehicle” comprising the “rights to life,
safety, and personal liberty; to belief, expression,
and conscience; and to privacy
and property,”24 this definition is itself
anything but free from any presupposition.
By generally rejecting theological
and metaphysical foundations of human
rights as counterproductive, Gregg also
obstructs one important way for some
people in some communities to access
human rights language. This contradicts
his pragmatic bias that puts emphasis
on achieving the desired results—the
implementation of human rights norms—
ideally from within a local community.
Finally, there is a serious tension
between Gregg’s claim to investigate
the subject in a realistic manner and
his strong emphasis on the necessity for
individuals to develop a “human rights
personality.” This personality is implicitly
based on inner consistency, rational insight
into the primacy of moral norms as
well as a high level of self-reflexivity. As
a result, Gregg is not able to completely
break the cycle of reproducing inequality
with regard to the implications of his
categories. With this line of reasoning he
also appears to be surprisingly close to
the Kantian tradition of political moralism
that realists such as Bernard Williams
or Raymond Geuss rebut by highlighting
people’s general inconsistency, the
historical specificity of political events
and institutions, and the importance of
power for social relations. Nonetheless,
Gregg’s analysis raises hopes for a new
wave of realistic and pragmatic, or at least
sociologically informed, investigations to
emerge within political theory that fruitfully
explores the preconditions and the
accessibility of human rights for people
living in a variety of political and cultural
environments.
René Wolfsteller*
University of Glasgow
Review 3: Human Rights as Social Construction
Critical Exchange on Human Rights as Social Construction by Benjamin Gregg
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011, 272 pp., ISBN: 978-1107612945
Contemporary Political Theory advance online publication, 20 May 2014;
doi:10.1057/cpt.2014.10
Andrew Koppelman:
Benjamin Gregg’s book, Human Rights as Social Construction, propounds an
understanding of human rights that is based upon ‘a wholly naturalistic conception’
of humanity, one ‘that takes human nature as biologically understood and eschews
supernatural explanations, whether theological or metaphysical’ (p. 185). He oscillates
between two conceptions of this project: an abstemious, neo-Rawlsian political
liberalism, and a comprehensive view that rejects religious and metaphysical claims.
The first, more modest version holds that any conception of human rights must at
least be consistent with, and ideally would emerge from, local norms: ‘the task of the
human rights project is to generate agreement on human rights in widely different
cultural and political contexts in which the advocated rights are attuned to local
distinctions, peculiarities, and preferences’ (p. 60). Speculative disagreement is not
important, because ‘human rights are best understood in terms of the pragmatic
imperative for desired results, as distinguished from, say, an epistemological
imperative for objective truth’ (p. 5).
That attention to local context is not inconsistent with ideas about the supernatural.
The smartest missionaries understand that, in order to proselytize effectively, you have
got to get to know the natives. People with different metaphysical assumptions can and
sometimes do converge on the same principles of human rights, but each of them gets
there by reference to her own comprehensive view. This is what John Rawls had in
mind when he argued for an ‘overlapping consensus’ on the principles of political
cooperation. In an overlapping consensus, they may disagree about the ultimate
foundations of the political principles that govern them, but they agree upon the
principles, those principles are moral ones, and they are affirmed on moral grounds (see
Rawls, 2005, pp. 144–150). Gregg sometimes sympathizes with this approach (p. 35).
The dominant theme of Gregg’s book, however, epitomized in the title, discards
Rawls’s deliberate reticence and declares that human rights is a social construction
and nothing else. ‘[T]ranscendental norms can only be a figment of the imagination’,
and ‘the moral self-ennoblement of human beings is precisely that of humankind
giving itself norms of social and political behavior’ (p. 4). This is the mirror image of
his principal adversaries, such as Michael Perry who claims that if human rights is
to be coherent it must have a religious foundation (see Perry, 2007).1 Gregg’s is
a coherent alternative to Perry.2
Gregg’s book is an energetically argued working out of a distinct position about
human rights, showing how endorsement of such rights can be developed on a purely
secular basis, rooted in local norms – for example, by reinterpreting traditional
understandings of kinship obligations (p. 96). It is an effective rejoinder to Perry’s
claim to show the True and Only Way. But it is the kind of thesis that Rawls carefully
stayed away from, because he understood that secularism is itself a comprehensive
view that could never command broad agreement. In its own way, it is (as Gregg says
of Perry) ‘cultural particularism masquerading as universalism’ (p. 20). Rawls would
have emphasized that Perry and Rorty both can support a just society, even if they
never agree on ultimate foundations. But Gregg wants to insist that Perry’s own basis
for human rights commitments be rejected.
The trouble seems to lie in Gregg’s unstated assumption that there needs to be not
only a set of agreed-on human rights, but also an agreed-on basis for those rights.
Social constructionism has a comparative advantage over religion as a candidate
for this job: ‘social constructions are not necessarily exclusive, but every religion is’
(p. 19). Some people may find social constructionism particularistic, but it is ‘never
as particular as any rival faith or as any argument grounded in revelation and rival
revelatory traditions’ (p. 21).
But why assume that this job needs to be filled at all? If there is agreement on
rights, why does there need to be agreement on their basis? Jacques Maritain
famously quipped, during the drafting of the Universal Declaration on Human
Rights, that ‘we agree about the rights but on condition no one asks us why’ (quoted
in Glendon, 2001, p. 77). Agreement was to be reached ‘not on the basis of common
speculative ideas, but on common practical ideas, not on the affirmation of one and
the same conception of the world, of man, and of knowledge, but upon the
affirmation of a single body of beliefs for guidance in action’ (Glendon, 2001,
pp. 77–78). Gregg, on the other hand, wants a single rationale, one that, if not
universal, can at least claim a large market share. Thus, a misconception of the
kind of universality to seek renders his argument self-defeatingly parochial.
Gregg’s rhetorical and ontological commitments sometimes collide, most clearly
when he takes up human rights in Islam. He repeatedly argues (mainly in Chapter 6)
that Muslim understandings can be reframed to allow for human rights. Muslims,
however (as well as the Christians Gregg admires, such as Las Casas (p. 43)), are
unlikely to agree that ‘the natural world contains no information about normative
systems’ (p. 39). They emphatically will not ‘reject any norm that claims validity as
a matter of supernatural revelation’ (p. 155, n. 31). Their view will look a lot like
Perry’s.
The notion of ‘empirical rationales’ (p. 91) for rights, rights ‘understood
biologically not metaphysically’ (p. 46), runs into the old Humean problem that you
cannot derive an ought from an is. Gregg repeatedly tries to claim, in various ways,
that human rights can somehow be derived from natural facts. They cannot. The
similarity of my DNA to yours (p. 4) does not entail that I have any obligations
toward you. Natural human dispositions can be the basis for cultural agreement on
human rights (pp. 41, 45 and Chapter 5), but the same dispositions enable everything
Gregg hates, from genocide to religion and metaphysics. He suggests that morality
might be grounded in ‘prudential reciprocity’, which ‘motivates behavior along the
lines of mutual benefit’ (p. 24), but torturers will cheerfully admit that they would not
want to be tortured themselves. He claims that the ‘idea of human health’ possesses
‘normative force’ (p. 198), which can guide efforts at genetic enhancement (p. 200).
‘Health’, however, is a contested concept. Sickness is deviancy from a norm.
The norm is not given by nature. The ‘blight’ that strikes corn is labeled a disease
because humans want the corn crop to survive; otherwise we would just talk about
the competition between two species.3 Health is simply a desirable state of affairs. Its
desirability is not a natural fact.
Nor is culture a reliable basis for human rights. He repeatedly insists that local
commitments ‘may’ or ‘might’ or ‘could possibly’ be a basis for human rights
(pp. 24, 49, 53, 60, 71, 96, 112). Certainly they could, and Gregg’s attention to the
various ways in which they could is a great strength of his book. But of course they
can be the basis for all sorts of behavior, including the atrocities that motivated
the human rights project in the first place.4 He offers many sensible reflections
about how local cultures can be transformed to make them human rights friendly,
but this project needs a prior commitment to such rights in order to motivate it.
Gregg needs to own up to the fact that his commitment to human rights is not
grounded in anything further, for the simple reason that any normative commitment
must at some point hit bedrock that demands no further justification. (Another
entailment of the Humean point that you cannot derive an is from an ought.) This is
a problem for Perry, who seems to think that belief in God shields him from the need
for justification, when of course the fact of God’s existence, without more, would
have no normative entailments either.5 (Satan does not doubt God’s existence.)
Perry’s commitment to human rights is more basic than his ontology. The same is
true of Gregg.
The bedrock character of human rights means that there is no way to guarantee that
everyone will agree about their validity. Gregg claims that ‘normatively thin human
rights do not require coercive promotion’ (p. 74), but soon admits that ‘the idea of
human rights must reject its own violation’ (p. 82) and that such rights, precisely because
they are socially constructed, ‘exist’ only if enforced’ (p. 93). You just have to take sides.
Gregg’s fallacy is the mirror image of Perry’s. Believers in human rights represent
one faction on the planet. The other faction is potent. And busy. We should be grateful
for allies, instead of scolding them that my moral narrative is better than yours.
Notes
1 I have criticized Perry’s claim elsewhere. See http://balkin.blogspot.com/2007/08/religion-and-humanrights.
html; http://balkin.blogspot.com/2007/08/partly-necessary-god.html.
2 The kind of argument Gregg offers has already been made familiar by Richard Rorty. See Rorty (1989).
Gregg’s account of the cultural basis of human rights, however, is much more thoroughly articulated
than Rorty’s.
3 See Bayer (1987, pp. 183–186).
4 At one point he acknowledges this: ‘Human nature biologically understood guarantees nothing in a
political way or otherwise in a value-driven sense’ (p. 114). But he still regards biology as somehow
relevant to his project.
5 See Dworkin (2013).
References
Bayer, R. (1987) Homosexuality and American Psychiatry: The Politics of Diagnosis, revised edn.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Dworkin, R. (2013) Religion without God. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Glendon, M.A. (2001) A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human
Rights. New York: Random House.
Perry, M. (2007) Toward a Theory of Human Rights: Religion, Law, Courts. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Rawls, J. (2005) Political Liberalism, expanded edn. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rorty, R. (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Andrew Koppelman
Northwestern University Law School, Chicago, Illinois 60611, USA
akoppelman@northwestern.edu
Reply to Koppelman’s review of Human Rights as Social Construction
I thank Andrew Koppelman for his generous attention to my work. One could not ask
for a more conscientious critic. He raises major issues and I am grateful for the
opportunity to respond, especially to his reading of five key points.
First, I do not assume, as necessary, some ‘set of agreed-on human rights’. Instead
I argue that (a) proponents should strive asymptotically toward as much agreement
on human rights as possible at any given time; (b) that human rights work best as
freely embraced by their addressees, rather than as imposed; and (c) that they work
best in terms of self-determining political community holding itself accountable in its
treatment of its members. Disagreement is always likely, for example about whether
to include social and economic rights, and if so, which ones. But advocacy is not
deficient if it provides scope for, and access to, on-going deliberation and choice in
making and revising decisions. A social constructionist approach does so better than
can theological approaches with largely determinate and fixed doctrine largely
accepted by its adherents.
With regard to my claims that advocacy must not be coercive, that human rights
must reject their own violation and that they exist only if enforced, Koppelman
misses three things. (a) Agreement in and of itself does not guarantee compliance,
and agreement is not necessary to motivate at least some human rights facilitative
belief and action. (b) A proposition (in the form of a right, for example) must exclude
its own violation as a condition of its coherence. (c) To say that a norm ‘exists’ only if
it is enforced is to say that what matters is not merely to interpret the world but to
change it: the point of human rights is their actualization in behavior.
Second, my project, says Koppelman, ‘needs a prior commitment to such rights in
order to motivate it’ and requires ‘an agreed-on basis for those rights’. But the
pragmatist goal is not for everyone to agree on a foundation for human rights but to
freely embrace and practice them on whatever basis.My ‘reflections about how local
cultures can be transformed to make them human rights friendly’ would generate
commitment, not presuppose it. For Koppelman, because ‘any normative commitment
must at some point hit bedrock that demands no further justification’, my
‘commitment to human rights is more basic than [my] ontology’. But in my project,
commitment and ontology are one because most human being today regard dignity,
equality, freedom from bodily and other harm as goods, certainly for herself and, not
implausibly, for others as well. So where Koppelman’s path is existential and
decisionist – ‘you just have to take sides’ – mine is rational and fallibilist: ‘truth’ or
‘justice’ at any given time refer to a temporary report from the field of experience and
inquiry, a ‘snapshot’ for current orientation, always revisable. Truth or justice are
neither impossible nor drained of their capacity to motivate behavior.
Third, Koppelman misconstrues social construction as just one more comprehensive
view no different from religion. He does so because two items elude him. First,
he fails to grasp social construction’s capacity to coexist with a wide range of
competing comprehensive doctrines. It can cooperate with persons of faith who share
the goal of advancing human rights. Second, this secular approach might win more
people, and a wider variety of people, for the human rights project than a theological
one, and Koppelman cannot see that winning people in this way in no way entails
discouraging theologically motivated human rights advocates from pursuing human
rights work.
I offer three ancillary claims about a related point at issue between us: according to
Koppelman, my social constructionist proposal displays the very problems I identify
in the theological approaches I criticize. (a) He believes my approach seeks to
dissuade the faithful from their faith. In fact, it seeks instead to re-frame current local
understandings and practices to render them more human rights friendly. Re-framing
does not ask the re-framer to abandon his or her beliefs as such but rather to seek
a different way to attain them in practice, if freely persuaded that doing so will better
achieve his or her own goals. Thus mothers who have their daughters’ genitalia cut
might be persuaded to mark the girls’ passage from girlhood to adulthood in a way
that does not have the unwanted consequence of making the girls ill.
(b) Koppelman does not see how social construction can acknowledge pluralism,
and embrace toleration, without insisting on any particular pregiven or traditional
normative, theological, or metaphysical outlook. He does not see that most persons
invested in supernatural revelation also accept claims of a very different sort, for
example those that lead to standard medical diagnosis and treatment.
(c) Koppelman fails to grasp that pragmatism can be just as committed as
theological approaches to particularistic, substantive moral views. But unlike
otherworldly routes, a pragmatist commitment does not place unnecessary hurdles
in the way of adherents of different traditions who might be persuaded to embrace
the human rights idea.
Fourth, I say that human nature, biologically understood, entails nothing
normative. Yet for Koppelman, I ‘still regard biology as somehow relevant’ to my
project. He is flat-out mistaken: I nowhere claim that ‘human rights can somehow be
derived from natural facts’. That the genome of any one human individual can
represent the genome of the species entails no moral norms but can be interpreted in
ways suggestive for the social construction of norms. For example, given that most
human rights abusers identify their victims in terms of their membership in particular
groups (religion, race, or caste, among others), the human rights idea may be
advanced if at least some abusers come to realize that such memberships are in fact
constructions whereas the species-wide genetic identity of all individuals is not. This
biological ‘is’ generates no normative ‘ought’; it opens up a human rights friendly
vantage point that will resonate with some people.
And while ‘natural human dispositions can be the basis for cultural agreement on
human rights’, Koppelman concedes, the ‘same dispositions enable everything …
from genocide to religion and metaphysics’. One wonders how dispositions to
sympathy, care or helpfulness might enable genocide (if directed to others; and
sympathy for one’s own tribe hardly entails barbarism toward other tribes). But
where dispositions enable religion, they provide a standpoint – one internal, not
imposed from outside – from which to identify and criticize human rights abusive
behavior allowed or encouraged in other areas of the same religion. To be sure, such
dispositions will not always do the work that human rights advocates hope for. Nor
will another possible resource for advancing human rights thinking: prudential
reciprocity. (As Koppelman notes, ‘torturers will cheerfully admit that they would
not want to be tortured themselves’.) But that a particular resource cannot guarantee
success, or might be deployed contrary to human rights, is simply a fact about the
limitations of resources. Koppelman’s entailment – to abandon resources if they
cannot guarantee success, or guarantee against misuse – is self-defeating. The same
argument holds for his charge against my exploration of culture as a possible
resource for the human rights project. Culture, he writes, is not a ‘reliable basis for
human rights’ but the ‘basis for all sorts of behavior, including the atrocities that
motivated the human rights project in the first place’. In fact, some cultural products
offer solid ground: the very idea of human rights, for example.
Fifth, Koppelman dismisses my argument that the desire to be healthy possesses
normative force. He urges instead that ‘sickness’ is nothing but a civilizational
construct, ‘deviancy from a norm not given by nature’, such that physical health is
nothing but a particular cultural preference, ‘not a natural fact’. But cancer,
Alzheimer’s, heart disease, strokes, diabetes, nephritis or influenza, for example, are
not merely parochial prejudices of this or that community. No community advocates
such conditions as desirable. Everyone views them as scourges. Afflicted persons
seek therapy and hope for cure. In this context, all participants invoke the same norm
of somatic health. Such universal purchase suggests an argument by analogy, and
some addressees of the human rights project will find it plausible: identical human
rights for identically embodied creatures, genetically identical at the species level.
According to Koppelman, a ‘misconception of the kind of universality to seek’
renders my proposal ‘self-defeatingly parochial’. Parochial means self-induced
limitation. But there is nothing parochial in social construction. Not if the goal is a
universal embrace of human rights as contingent achievement in hard-fought social
movements, domestic legislation and international instruments. And there is nothing
parochial in interpretive overlays of the common desire for health.
Benjamin Gregg
University of Texas-Austin, Austin, Texas 78712, USA
bgregg@austin.utexas.edu
Review 4: Human Rights as Social Construction
Michael Goodhart. 2014. "Recent Works on Dignity and Human Rights: A Road Not Taken," Perspectives on Politics, v. 12, n. 4, pp. 486-856
Dignity in Adversity: Human Rights in Troubled Times. By Seyla Benhabib. Cambridge: Polity, 2011. 288p. $69.95
cloth, $24.95 paper.
Human Rights as Social Construction. Benjamin Gregg. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2012. 272p. $99.00
cloth, $27.99 paper.
Human Dignity. By George Kateb. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011. 256p. $22.95.
Dignity: Its History and Meaning. By Michael Rosen. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2012. 200p.
$21.95.
The Justice Cascade: How Human Rights Prosecutions Are Changing World Politics. By Kathryn Sikkink.
New York: W. W. Norton, 2011. 352p. $27.95 cloth, $25.62 paper.
Making Rights Claims: A Practice of Democratic Citizenship. By Karen Zivi. New York: Oxford University Press,
2012. 176p. $99.00 cloth, $24.95 paper.
Today the concepts of human rights and human
dignity have become “conjoined twins.”1 Dignity
is ubiquitous, invoked in discussions of everything
from the ethics of stem cell research to dwarf tossing
(a near obsession among writers on this topic) and the prodemocracy
demonstrations in Cairo’s Tahrir Square.
Prominent philosophers and political theorists—including
Ronald Dworkin, Jeremy Waldron, James Griffin, Jürgen
Habermas, and Rainer Forst—have recently used human
dignity to ground or expound upon their preferred
philosophical conceptions of human rights. If nothing
else, these are good times for Giovanni Pico della
Mirandola, whose 1486 “Oration on the Dignity of
Man” is trending.
While this surge of interest in human dignity is
noteworthy in itself, I shall not attempt to trace its
origins or to provide an overview of the concept’s various
contemporary uses.2 Instead, I want to consider what
recent works on dignity reveal about the study of human
rights within our discipline. When I began my graduate
studies nearly 20 years ago, human rights were still in the
margins of political science; today they have become
central to it. Within political theory, human rights figure
prominently in debates on justice, democracy, and
accountability; in world and comparative politics, rights
are studied by scholars working on diverse topics,
including security, development, political economy,
international law and organization, social movements,
norm diffusion, and comparative democratization. Only
the subfield of American politics remains largely indifferent
to human rights.
Despite this mainstreaming of human rights within
political science, theoretical and empirical research on the
subject remains stubbornly segregated. Empiricists typically
treat the normative importance of rights as selfevident,
while normative scholars typically neglect the
boisterous political life of rights in their search for the
elusive justification or moral foundation that they remain
persuaded are lacking. This division is outmoded and
counterproductive: The politics of human rights might
well hold clues to their appeal and legitimacy, providing an
alternative route for apprehending their normative character;
likewise, their normative character seems indispensable
for making sense of the politics and institutions they
enliven.
Dignity seems to illustrate this point vividly. Not only
is it a hot topic in political theory—five of the six volumes
under review here are written by theorists—but recent
events have thrust it to the forefront of today’s politics. To
name just a few examples: Dignity has been frequently
invoked in the Arab uprisings, by peasant and indigenous
movements from various parts of the globe, and in
antiausterity politics in Europe (think of Spain’s tellingly
named indignados). Yet if dignity points in the direction of
the integrated study of human rights within political
science, it is a signpost for a road (so far) not taken.
These books, at least, mostly bypass it—and mostly to
their detriment. George Kateb and Michael Rosen take the
well-traveled philosophical route; rather than a bridge to
politics, dignity for them becomes a kind of bypass of it.
Benjamin Gregg and Kathryn Sikkink take different
constructivist paths: Gregg’s leads him inadvertently back
to philosophy; Sikkink’s takes her right to the bridge, but
she misses the turn. Only Seyla Benhabib and Karen Zivi
explore this road, with Zivi venturing a little farther. Still,
their work offers a map to an integrated political science of
human rights.
Kateb begins his Human Dignity by declaring that the
defense of rights at present requires little theoretical
articulation (pp. 1–2). Why, he asks, “make trouble by
defending human rights at length and make worse trouble
by claiming that human dignity is the basis, or part of
the basis, for human rights?” (p. 2). His answer is a little
surprising, especially in light of his admission that “actual
progress in realizing human rights . . . has often come
about without much need or use of theoretical assistance”
(p. 3). Kateb believes that opposition to human rights
from the radical Left, from utilitarians, and from virtue
ethicists—all of whom are on the side of the great majority
of the people—must be reckoned with. (The surprise
is that these objections have been thoroughly addressed
in 20-plus years of scholarship.)3 This project positions
him as indifferent to the politics of dignity and human
rights: there are by his own admission no practical
problems to be solved here, and he is willing to risk
making trouble for human rights in the pursuit of his
theoretical ambition.
Dignity, Kateb argues, provides an existential ground
for respect for human rights independent of the moral
grounds for respecting them. This is not to deny a close
relation to morality. The point is, rather, that “for many
people, and rightly, morality has to do solely or principally
with human suffering; but human dignity in its concern
with status and stature has to do with the proper
recognition of the identity of every human being and the
identity of the human species” (pp. 12–13). Morally,
rights reduce suffering; existentially, they recognize the
identity of all people as humans of equal status (p. 22).
Violations of human dignity have existential weight
independent of suffering itself, Kateb maintains, weight
that lies in the phenomenon of degradation (p. 16). To be
treated as not human is importantly different from
suffering (p. 17). So while the moral component in the
defense of rights (concern for suffering) is necessary, it is
not sufficient (p. 33). The existential component (concern
for dignity) adds two dimensions to this defense: First, it
highlights a particular attitude toward human beings
manifest in the infliction of suffering. Second, it emphasizes
the diminishment or deformation that people experience
when they endure harsh and needless suffering
(p. 36); this dehumanization often leads to rights violations
(p. 39). The author illustrates these points in an
enlightening discussion of Aldous Huxley’s Brave New
World, a dystopia in which there is no immorality but in
which human dignity is nonetheless effaced (pp. 40 ff.).
Kateb mostly ignores the intriguing political implications
of his arguments, sticking with his theoretical
defense of human rights. How and how much his
arguments help remains unclear; they certainly do not
do much to answer the leftist critique (they are somewhat
more useful against the utilitarian and virtue-ethicist
challenges; see pp. 91 ff.). They do, however, make
trouble for proponents of economic and social rights, in
three ways.
First, Kateb rejects absolute Lockean ownership rights,
calling “[claims] to a completely unregulated and barely
taxed right of property” unacceptable (p. 52). He further
asserts that “the right of life can be the basis to circumscribe
the right of property, so as to help many stay alive
and in conditions that are not miserable, and not die
before their time from preventable causes” (p. 52).
Moreover, since property is not quite the same kind
of right as other rights, taxing it, “especially for relief
of the poor,” represents no genuine conflict of rights
(p. 52). The author may regard these statements as
supportive of social and economic rights (though more
in reply to critics on the Right, it seems); in any case,
his Dickensian vocabulary and attitude toward “the
poor” have the unhelpful ring of nineteenth-century
charity appeals.
Second, Kateb argues that “the major human rights are
found most purely and economically stated not in recent
charters but in the US Constitution” (p. 28). This could
only conceivably be true if social and economic rights do
not count among the “major human rights,” since the
Constitution is silent on them. He has a legitimate concern
about the statist implications of recent charters, which
permit the derogation of rights in times of national
emergency or in the public interest (p. 29). But defining
human rights—and, by implication, human dignity—as
unconnected to social and economic rights is unhelpful (to
say the least) to advocates and unlikely to blunt leftist
criticism of them as “bourgeois rights.”
Third, in discussing claims of global distributive
justice, Kateb argues that a just society must defer the
great achievements that contribute to human stature and
instead focus resources on addressing poverty. Yet the
equation is different with respect to global poverty. Kateb
doubts that “the claims of stature in the form of great
achievements in the present can be sacrificed to the project
of redistributing as much wealth as possible to alleviate
global poverty.” He sees “an important difference between
initiating and maintaining an exploitative policy or
condition . . . and neglecting to redress it when one does
not have direct responsibility for it” (p. 183). On
a charitable reading, this argument might permit the
redistribution of some wealth (if not as much as possible)
and, assuming an expansive, critical understanding of
direct responsibility, license significant global povertyreduction
efforts. Still, this position is even more insular
and radical than the social liberalism of theorists like John
Rawls and David Miller.4 Kateb effectively accepts global
poverty as the price we pay for great achievements. It is
unclear to me how he figures these sums—and how much
existential affirmation impoverished people find in monuments
or space stations.5 Again, Kateb is not doing global
antipoverty advocates any favors here; if anything, he is
fueling leftist critiques of human rights. That said, he
certainly delivers on his pledge to make trouble by
defending them.
Arguably, Kateb’s principal aim is to give a defense of
human dignity based in human stature. His “justification”
of humanity is itself remarkable, and I present it in his
words: “[T]here is no species like humanity. It is capable of
doing not just a few remarkable things that no other
species can—the same is true of many other species—but
an indefinitely large number of remarkable things that no
other species can” (p. 113). “Only humanity can perform
the three indispensable functions: keep the record of
nature, understand nature, and appreciate it. The human
species, alone among species on earth, can perform these
services to nature on earth and beyond” (p. 114). Performing
these functions is the only thing that could justify
humanity in the eyes of an external judge, “which perceives
with the most complete understanding, cannot be selfinterested
(or not only so), and must devote itself to what is
real and not itself, and do so with the high intellectual and
aesthetic virtues of magnanimity, wonder, and gratitude”
(p. 113). This judge (upholding the highest human
standards) would appreciate that “nature, understood as
distinct from humanity, would be worse off without it
because humanity can do for nature in the comprehensive
sense—the earth and the universe—what must be
done, but cannot be done otherwise than by humanity”
(pp. 113–14). In case our stewardship of nature is not
enough, “it is also the case that . . . the human species can
receive another nonmoral justification—justification by
great achievements—that does not depend on the ability
to be selfless, as toward nature” (p. 115).
The problem with great achievements is that they are
premised upon treating “the great mass of people
poorly”—hence, the trade-off between justice and pyramids.
This is partly because “the innate ability of human
beings to contribute to great achievements appears to be
unequal” (p. 174). In fact, democratic culture, which
precludes violations of rights in the service of great
achievements, thereby “[jeopardizes] human stature”
(p. 175). Kateb conceptualizes this historical tension as
a conflict between dignity as status, which requires equal
treatment, and dignity as stature, which requires massive
social inequalities in the service of humanity’s “great
achievements.” His rueful conclusion is that while democrats
can ignore past violations of rights in celebrating
human accomplishments, today we must prioritize rights
(domestically, anyway). Kateb tries to console himself by
mustering some enthusiasm for the achievements of
American culture in the humanities (he frequently equates
“democratic” and “American” throughout the book), but
this is about the most he can manage: “films made for
smaller audiences are complex and subtle enough to
deserve a long life. I do not want to quarrel with that or
with the greatness of some jazz” (p. 203).
It is hard to assess this second argument, which is at
times brilliant, bombastic, creative, curmudgeonly, sublime,
self-indulgent, and, frankly, a little bizarre. I shall
make only two points. First, justifying human existence
by reference to our stewardship of nature, given current
trends, is a bit like foxes justifying their existence by
citing their protection of henhouses. Besides, by Kateb’s
own admission, nature has no idea we are recording or
understanding or appreciating it; this justification reflects
the same species arrogance that, it seems to me, has put us
and our planet on an expressway to ecological calamity.
Second, it is telling that Kateb finds the political commitment
to equal human status insufficient to condemn the
evils of degradation and to justify human rights. His appeal
to human status and great achievements betrays profound
misgivings about democracy.
Rosen’s Dignity also posits a close theoretical connection
between dignity and human rights. “Dignity is central
to modern human rights discourse,” Rosen observes, “the
closest that we have to an internationally accepted
framework for the normative regulation of political life,
and it is embedded in numerous constitutions, international
conventions, and declarations” (pp. 1–2). Yet
despite this prominence, Rosen regards human rights as
“obviously deeply puzzling—almost everyone nowadays
professes commitment to them, yet few people would
claim that they had a good, principled account of what
they are and why we have them” (p. 54; my emphasis).
Unlike Kateb, Rosen is skeptical whether dignity can help
make the case for human rights; in the end, it is unclear
whether he thinks human rights make a case worth
helping. He certainly doubts that any of the three
important historical meanings of dignity—as status or
rank, as a “transcendental kernel” of incomparable moral
worth within all human beings, and as appropriate,
graceful comportment (pp. 11–38)—can provide a “good,
principled account” of human rights. Such an account has
three requirements. It must “explain and justify the claim
that all human beings share ‘inviolable’ dignity and that
they are ‘free and equal’ in that dignity”; “show that it
follows from this that they also have inviolable and
inalienable rights”; and, “identify what those rights [are]”
(p. 54).
Rosen suggests—in direct opposition to Jeremy
Waldron6—that status will not get us very far in this
respect. Although Kant’s transcendental kernel looks more
promising, Rosen rejects it as well (on which more later).
The notion of dignified bearing, by contrast, he finds
more promising than it seems. Pursuing this prospect, he
develops a fourth interpretation, one that yields a right to
have one’s dignity respected; while this is a very important
right, Rosen concludes, it cannot provide a foundation for
rights in general (pp. 55–62).
One of Rosen’s main arguments is that none of the
received understandings of dignity can adequately ground
human rights. I have no particular quarrel with this
conclusion, but I find the question more revealing. His
search for philosophical foundations for human rights is
motivated by the worry that without them, human rights
are somehow incoherent or untenable. Human rights must
presumably lack adequate foundations at present; otherwise
there would be no point to the search. Yet by Rosen’s own
admission, human rights are accepted by almost everyone;
are embedded in many constitutions, treaties, and deliberations;
and provide an international normative framework
for regulating politics—they are neither incoherent nor
untenable. So it is hard to see why, exactly, human rights
need philosophical foundations. Indeed, some proponents
of human rights regard their lack of clear philosophical
grounding as essential to their political viability. As Jacques
Maritain, a prominent member of the UNESCO committee
that drafted the Universal Declaration of Human
Rights, famously remarked: “Yes, we agree about the rights,
on the condition that no one ask us why.”
Rosen apparently sees little connection between the
evident empirical success of human rights and their
normative status or grounding; in this respect, his study
reflects and perpetuates the division in the discipline. He
does consider at length some recent legal cases involving
dignity, among them the (in)famous Wackenheim
(dwarf-tossing) case and several framed by Germany’s
constitutional recognition of dignity as a fundamental and
inviolable principle. Even here, however, Rosen’s primary
interest is in the Kantian “transcendental kernel” view,
which he finds inadequate because it cannot explain or
justify the various rulings he considers. Questions about
the political fallout from these rulings or their effects on
the legitimacy of rights are ignored.
The argument is anyway rather odd. The German high
court might claim that it is relying on a Kantian kernel
view, but if its decisions seem inconsistent with or poorly
explained by this view, that is a problem for the court,
not the kernel—unless Rosen can provide some independent
basis for concluding that the judgments are correct
but their reasoning flawed. Otherwise, it could be that the
court has simply failed in properly interpreting the kernel
or adequately articulating its relevance in a particular case.
Rosen proposes that his own interpretation of dignity,
with its emphasis on “the value of the symbolic or expressive
aspects of our behavior toward others” (p. 126), makes
better sense of what the court is doing. This might be right,
and it might reflect what the court is really thinking, but it
leaves the kernel uncracked.
The last part of the book considers the question of
whether we owe respect to corpses and fetuses—or, more
generally, whether “we owe such duties [of respect] only to
persons” (p. 128). Rosen finds the “universally held belief
that we have a duty to treat dead bodies with respect”
deeply puzzling and important for moral philosophy. He
asks whether our duty to respect the dignity of humanity
has to benefit anyone and whether it is a duty owed to
anyone, concluding that it does not and is not (p. 140).
In answering these questions, he develops a duty-based
conception of morality based in respect for humanity,
a conception that he argues we should also attribute to
Kant: “[I]nstead of starting from the question what
maxims can be universalized without contradiction, it
would be better to understand Kant as asking first how we
have to act in order to treat our dignity (our inner kernel of
intrinsic value) with the proper respect” (p. 147).
I am in no position to say whether this would in fact be
a better interpretation of Kant. I do wonder, however,
whether this formulation—which boils down to something
worryingly like an injunction to treat our dignity with
dignity—really does much work. Rosen’s other formulations
seem equally empty: For instance, dignity “requires
that we behave in ways that ‘honor’ or ‘respect’ humanity in
our person” (p. 153), a requirement that he concedes
provides “no clear test or set of criteria” for determining
appropriate action (p. 155). The criteria are apparently clear
enough to resolve the corpse question, however: “we might
have [a duty to respect humanity] toward things—corpses
or fetuses, for example—that are not themselves human and
will not benefit fromour behavior toward them,” even if we
abandon Kant’s transcendental perspective (p. 157). Rosen
avoids direct engagement with politics, sticking to Kant and
corpses and remaining coy about what respect for fetuses
entails. This is a shame, because the politics of abortion,
stem cells, torture, or other contentious examples of dignity
politics might enliven and fortify his rarefied discussion.
Instead, he cruises along on his philosophical fly-over,
ignoring the numerous off-ramps that would give him
access to political points of interests on the angry, congested
surface streets below.
One might expect the two self-avowedly constructivist
works under review here to handle the integration of
normative and empirical aspects of human rights more
deftly. After all, constructivists are broadly concerned
with the creation, diffusion, and effectiveness of norms
(and other things). Yet as Gregg’s Human Rights as Social
Construction and Sikkink’s The Justice Cascade show,
constructivist work often takes place on one side or the
other of this divide. The expectation of integration arises
from the casual association of constructivism with norms –
which can refer either to an empirical phenomenon in the
world or to the normativity (the “oughtness”) of a concept.
In international relations, most constructivist work on
human rights falls, like Sikkink’s, on the empirical side of
the divide, philosophical constructivism like Gregg’s on
the normative side. The problematic features of this divide
are clear in these two otherwise engaging books.
Gregg rejects traditional philosophical approaches to
human rights as “theological” and “otherworldly” (p. 3)
and seeks a “social constructionist” alternative. I find most
of his critique of metaphysical conceptions of rights
insightful and persuasive. His chapter on the incompatibility
of global human rights with the nation-state as
presently conceived and configured is a must-read for all
serious students of human rights. That said, I have
reservations about his “human rights project” and about
the political fallout from it.
What Gregg calls social constructionism (constructivism)
entails that we regard the objects of our analysis as
products of human social interaction—that we treat the
“facts” in question as socially determined and variable. He
rejects Rawlsian-style philosophical construction, which
builds up conclusions from moral assumptions, as hopelessly
metaphysical, detached from social and political
reality. Gregg attempts to use social constructivism to
explain the universal validity and bindingness of human
rights—a bold attempt, given that social constructivism is
frequently aligned (if not allied) with cultural relativism.
He tries to square this circle through the idea of contingent
empirical universality, which essentially says that human
rights will become universally binding only if all communities
willingly embrace them. Their local acceptance
becomes a possible empirical basis for a future, though
contingent, universality. Gregg offers a vision of human
rights as noncoercive and nonimperialistic, based on locally
valid norms but potentially universal (pp. 135 ff.). On his
account, human rights inform a proper understanding of
dignity, rather than the other way round. He dismisses
conceptions of dignity invoked by philosophers, seeing
them as examples of the “theological approach to human
rights” that he hopes to overturn (p. 17). In his account,
“the traditional notion that some persons possess dignity
becomes the posttraditional idea that all persons possess it”
(p. 46). Dignity is thus situated within and shaped by the
“political, social, and legal categories of recognition in local
communities (and potentially across communities)”; rather
than reflecting some metaphysical essence, human dignity
becomes a political achievement (p. 46).
All of this is quite appealing and seems like just the
kind of integrated normative and empirical approach
I have been calling for. Unfortunately, things go wonky
in the follow-through. Gregg seems mainly interested in
providing an account of human rights that he thinks
could or should command future consensus, rather than
in studying local understandings of rights or exploring
possible terms of their translation and negotiation.
Instead of investigating the local bases for the acceptability
of rights and seeking similarities and potential
bridges among them, he offers his own eclectic grounding,
drawing on neurobiology and a doctrine of assertive
selfhood (pp. 91–99) to construct a highly idealized
account. He even explains how activists might develop
“indigenous” interpretations of rights as he understands
them (p. 141). In the end, this is less a book about human
rights as a social construction than it is about how to
construct human rights along the lines Gregg thinks or
hopes will attract universal support—a philosophical construct
with assembly instructions.
In a further irony, Gregg’s social constructivism yields
an account with no politics in it: He describes the work
that politics might do in advancing the ideal human rights
project but pays no attention to the present politics
surrounding human rights or to how politics might
impede the human rights project (without almost any
consideration of politics, I should say). Apparently to
advance his account’s acceptability, Gregg makes some
puzzling and worrisome concessions on democracy and
on women’s rights.7 Briefly, Gregg disputes Jürgen
Habermas’s claims about the co-originality of democracy
and human rights and questions Jack Donnelly’s assertions
about democracy’s importance for the effective realization
of human rights (pp. 97–98). The author wants to insist
that human rights can emerge even in nondemocratic
societies, and so they can, but he confuses the conditions
of rights’ emergence with the requirements for their
maintenance, wrongly concluding that human rights
neither need nor require democracy. On women’s rights,
Gregg condones women’s inequality and subordination
so long as the women “embrace” it.8 He argues that
“a community that discriminates against some of its
members in ways that do not constitute persecution, and
in ways accepted by those discriminated against,
should be respected in its choice and organization”
(p. 22). If “respect” here simply rules out invoking
women’s rights as a pretext for military adventurism,
fine. Gregg, however, wants to “rule in” baselines for
women’s rights that fall well short of social, political, or
economic equality and that license women’s subordination
and relegation to the private sphere.9
The broader question is why an ideal account like
Gregg’s should sacrifice anything on the altar of acceptability.
He insists that his approach enables a critical stance
on our culture and on others, yet I cannot see how these
concessions are consistent with such a stance or how they
can be reconciled with the conceptual architecture of his
theory. (How, for instance, does women’s subordination
square with the assertive selfhood at the foundation of
human rights?) If, as Gregg avows, “[h]uman rights can be
legitimate for any community that comes to embrace
them” (p. 158), why presume that democracy and
women’s rights are somehow especially problematic?
Greater attention to the political claims and struggles of
feminists and of opponents of authoritarianism might have
helped him avoid these difficulties.
Sikkink provides a very different constructivist reading
of human rights. She recounts the emergence of the
“dramatic new trend in world politics toward holding
individual state officials, including heads of state, criminally
accountable for human rights violations” (p. 5). The justice
cascade does not indicate that perfect justice is being done
or will be done, Sikkink stresses, and it does not mean that
most perpetrators of human rights violations are being held
criminally accountable: “Rather, justice cascade means that
there has been a shift in the legitimacy of the norm of
individual criminal accountability for human rights violations
and an increase in criminal prosecutions on behalf of
that norm. The term captures how the idea started as a small
stream, but later caught on suddenly, sweeping along many
actors” (p. 5). She recognizes that this cascade is hardly
inevitable, and the book is her attempt to determine how
and why it developed.
Unlike the other titles under review here, The Justice
Cascade is primarily an empirical study. Sikkink’s vast
knowledge and experience and her distinctive narrative
voice make the book both accessible and deeply personal,
and it is full of insights and largely persuasive. It is also
somewhat unusual among empirical studies in taking
a clear ethical stance on its subject matter (in advocating
prosecutions). The author notes that in the view of most
(empirical) political scientists, doing so compromises one’s
objectivity and undermines the credibility of one’s
research. For a long time, she writes, she thought that
addressing ethical questions would require her to “[s]top
being a researcher and become a moral philosopher”
(p.229; I assume she meant to say something more like
“give up on my own present research agenda”). Now she
has “identified an approach that [lets her] combine
attention to both normative issues and empirical research
findings” (p. 229). This approach is consequentialism,
which she defines as the view that “knowledge of the
expected consequences is important for helping to make
hard ethical choices” (p. 230). Prosecutions are good if
they promote democracy and stability.
It is not clear whether this consequentialism explains
the spread of norms of accountability, however. Sikkink
understands norms as standards of appropriate behavior
that carry a special quality of “oughtness”—which, I argue
later, cannot be explained on consequentialist grounds.
Norms are intersubjective, and often only a small number
of people share them; they can spread rapidly, or cascade,
when norm entrepreneurs push for their widespread
recognition (p. 11). The justice cascade refers only to
individual legal accountability for human rights violations,
though this norm is nested within wider global movements:
the “human rights revolution” and the related push for
transitional justice (p. 16) made possible by the third wave
of democratization and the end of the Cold War (p. 24).
Three streams feed this cascade: domestic and foreign
prosecutions of human rights violations, international
prosecutions, and the “streambed of hard law,” made up
of international human rights conventions (p. 97).10 The
book traces the origins of each stream, carrying us from
Greece and Portugal, whence domestic prosecutions did
not diffuse, to Argentina and Latin America, whence they
did; from Nuremberg and Tokyo to the ad hoc tribunals
for Yugoslavia and Rwanda and the Pinochet case; and
from the Genocide Conventions and Geneva accords of
the late 1940s through the conventions against Apartheid
and Torture in the 1980s. These streams have merged into
what Sikkink describes as a decentralized, interactive
system of global accountability whose most notable
features are the doctrine of universal jurisdiction and the
creation, via the Rome Statute of 1998, of the International
Criminal Court (97 ff.).
The book tackles three big questions related to this
cascade: The first concerns the origins of new ideas
regarding individual criminal accountability for human
rights violations; the second concerns how and why some
ideas and practices become norms and diffuse; the third
concerns the effects of human rights prosecutions (p. 230).
With respect to the third question, Sikkink challenges
the skepticism about human rights trials that pervades the
conventional wisdom and scholarly literature on political
transitions. This skeptical view fears that the threat of
prosecution spurs the bad guys to entrench themselves
ever more deeply in power and inculcates damaging
political instability (pp. 130–60). She finds little evidence
to support these anxieties; in fact, her own data show
(though not definitively) that human rights trials are
beneficial for democracy, contribute to the rule of law,
and promote political stability—this is the consequentialist
case for trials (pp. 229 ff.).
With respect to the second big question, Sikkink argues
that to explain why change happens, we need to pay
attention to “how agents—that is, real people and
organizations—promote new ideas and practices” and how,
over time, these can create a “new understanding of the ways
in which states ought to behave, and new understandings
of the national interests of states (p. 237). This account,
which she describes as “agentic constructivism” (p. 237),
accommodates top-down diffusion and bottom-up and
horizontal diffusion, both of which figure into the justice
cascade (though the book focuses on the former).
Sikkink’s answer to the first big question is that systemic
shocks and changes in the domestic balance of power
account for the origins of new ideas about individual
criminal accountability (p. 245). Curiously, this reads
more like a further explanation of norm diffusion than like
an account of the origins or appeal of new ideas. I think
that the cascade metaphor is implicated here: One can
trace the streams that feed a cascade back to their sources,
noting their particular paths, but this does not explain why
they flow in the first place; to know that, we have to get
under the surface. Put differently, explaining the diffusion
of norms is not an empirical question of tracking their
proliferation; it also has to do with the nature and appeal of
the norms themselves—with their “oughtness.” On the
author’s account, this cannot be a function of their
consequences; we can only know these after the norms
diffuse.
Sikkink acknowledges this difficulty indirectly, at the
book’s end, when she asks “why certain ideas at certain
moments in certain places, resonate, grab attention, and
become possible”—a problem she calls the “single most
difficult” one raised in her analysis (p. 261). This, finally, is
a direct engagement with the first big question. Sikkink
argues that issues involving bodily harm are the most likely
to fuel “transnational activist campaigns because such
wrongs resonate across cultures and societies. The crimes
for which individual criminal accountability is sought
involve exactly this subset of violent bodily harms”
(p. 255), owing to the obvious injustice they involve.
She also makes frequent reference to the “intrinsic power”
of new norms and to the “inherently appealing” ideas that
animate prosecutions (p. 231). She claims to find nothing
puzzling in the intrinsic appeal of the human rights idea—
the idea that “almost everyone would prefer to be alive
than dead, free than imprisoned, secure than tortured, fed
than hungry. Core human rights norms have resonated so
profoundly in the world in part because of this intrinsic
appeal” (pp. 261–62). She complains that “while psychologists
can speak of . . . a ‘moral instinct,’ this is still heresy”
for political scientists (p. 261).
There are two problems here. First, this kind of
bootstrapping might be enough to ground protections
against murder, torture, and arbitrary imprisonment, but
it seems radically insufficient in the case of more controversial
rights. What if “almost everyone” does not agree
about the importance of press freedom or reproductive
rights or the dignity of lesbian, gay, bisexual, transgender,
and queer people or the right to health care or an adequate
standard of living? Second, if Sikkink really thinks that
human rights are matters of moral or psychological fact,
why does she find it so hard to account for their diffusion?
Why does she find it “surprising to watch how uniformly
human beings—even those embedded in cultural scenarios
that tell them otherwise—believe that they are entitled
to something better” (p. 262) when they experience
human rights abuses? Indeed, if human rights are
inherently powerful, intrinsically appealing, moral or
psychological facts, why are they not ubiquitous, selfexecuting?
Sikkink’s answer is power (p. 235). This is
plausible enough, but it calls for a much more fully
developed moral psychology to explain why the intrinsic
appeal of human rights and the moral instinct is absent or
deficient or overwhelmed in some individuals, why
human rights norms (rather than some other ones) prove
useful and appealing as tools to counteract power, and how
persuasion and diffusion work in the case of “non-obvious”
rights. Such an account, if it is available, spans the normative
and the empirical.
The final two books I consider make the turn toward
an integrated account of human rights, though both have
only begun down this road. In Dignity in Adversity,
Benhabib takes up, like Gregg, questions about the validity
of universal human rights norms in local settings. She
conceptualizes the problem primarily as one of reconciling
cosmopolitan norms with territorially demarcated, democratic
popular sovereignty, an approach that raises many
questions. For instance, is a demos of the kind she imagines
necessary or justifiable on democratic grounds? Is this
binary framework of the universal and particular adequate
for making sense of transnational and supranational legal
and policy issues—those that involve or cut across many
demoi, not all of which share the same presuppositions
about the validity of cosmopolitan norms? Is this
depiction of the global political economy and world
system conceptually and empirically rich enough to
provide significant analytic leverage on the problem of
social and economic emancipation that Benhabib
believes is central to the struggle for human dignity
(pp. 192 ff.)?11
Dignity’s marquee status notwithstanding, it makes only
rare appearances in the book. Nonetheless, there is a conception
of human dignity at work throughout these essays
in the idea of communicative freedom, which Benhabib
anchors in an enlarged understanding of Hannah Arendt’s
“right to have rights.” Benhabib argues that a political
justification of human rights presupposes what she calls
justificatory universalism, which requires “the acknowledgement
of the communicative freedom of the other, that is, of
the right of the other to accept as legitimate only those
norms as rules of action of whose validity she has been
convinced with reasons” (p. 11). This acknowledgment
rests in turn on moral universalism, which is “equal respect
for the other as a being capable of communicative freedom”—
the right to have rights (p. 11).
Benhabib insists that this moral universalism does not
determine a specific list of rights “beyond the protection
of the communicative freedom of the person” (p. 11).
That protection, however, entails quite a lot. It would, she
argues (p. 127), “minimally” include
the rights to life, liberty (including to freedom from slavery,
serfdom, forced occupation, as well as protecting against sexual
violence and sexual slavery); the right to some form of personal
property; equal freedom of thought (including religion), expression,
association, representation, and the right to self-government.
Furthermore, liberty requires provisions for the “equal value
of liberty” (Rawls), through the guarantee of some bundle of
socio-economic goods, including adequate provisions of basic
nourishment, shelter, and education.
In accepting Habermas’s discourse principle (p. 129),
Benhabib envisions a “veto” for all citizens and residents that
allows them to “demand that the conversation of justification
resume and not be terminated unless their objections
have been voiced, listened to, and resolved upon” (p. 159).
Benhabib argues that her account avoids metaphysical
entanglements because it is a “presuppositional” analysis of
rights. What this means is basically that my recognition of
your right to have rights is a precondition of (presupposes)
your being able to contest and accept my rights in the first
place. I have my doubts whether this argument holds up,
but I leave those worries aside here. The much more
interesting parts of the book, I think, are those in which the
author discusses how rights create a normative universe of
meaning. She argues that the profusion of human rights law
and treaties and the uptake of human rights norms by actors
outside formal legal and legislative arenas facilitate new
forms of public claimsmaking and anticipate “new forms of
justice to come” (pp. 15, 125). Benhabib calls this the
“jurisgenerative” potential of rights.12
“Democratic iteration” is the process through which this
tension between the unity and diversity of human rights is
worked out—that is, in which the relation between the
moral core and legal form of rights is articulated and
negotiated (p. 73). Through public iterations of will and
opinion formation, rights are appropriated and contextualized
by democratic communities (pp. 73–75); rights acquire
legitimacy—though not validity—through the exercise of
democratic popular sovereignty (p. 118), which exercise
itself presupposes the communicative freedom that rights
both enable and express (p. 74).
The contrast with Gregg’s approach is illuminating.
He attempts to erase the tension between universal and
particular by defining the universal as the sum of the
particular: human rights attain universal validity only
when they command local validity everywhere. Benhabib,
we might say, seeks to inhabit rather than to resolve the
tension, to work out how universal and particular inform
each other in processes of negotiating rights. This analysis
is most penetrating and illuminating when Benhabib
attends to the generative power of cosmopolitan norms
and focuses on the potential for rights- and justiceenhancing
iterations (as well as pathological ones) in the
give-and-take of democratic politics. This “cosmopolitanism
without illusions” (p. 16) highlights how rights and
identity get negotiated and renegotiated through political
contestation and how this process can bestow legitimacy
on rights in particular contexts—as illustrated in an
illuminating discussion of debates surrounding secularism
and the public wearing of headscarves in France, Germany,
and Turkey (Chapter 9).
Critics have questioned whether democratic iteration is
a normative or an empirical concept; Benhabib’s reply—
that it has both empirical and normative components,
“as all ‘legitimacy’ concepts since Max Weber attest to”
(p. 151)—leaves unclear whether she understands the
concept to be descriptive. She often writes as if it were—
for instance, in characterizing democratic iterations as
“[involving] complex processes of public argument,
deliberation, and exchange through which universalist
rights claims are contested and contextualized, invoked
and revoked, posited and positioned throughout legal and
political institutions, as well as in the associations of civil
society” (p. 16; see also p. 182). At other times, however,
democratic iteration is deployed as “a normative concept
with empirical import” that allows us to judge contentious
discourses according to normative criteria deriving their
justification from communicative ethics (p. 16). So, while
democratic iteration refers to the processes of collective
self-appropriation of cosmopolitan norms through which
rights lose their parochialism, it also provides the critical
standard for assessing whether genuinely democratic
iterations are occurring: “democratic iterations themselves
presuppose some standards of rights [those entailed by
communicative freedom]” (p. 129).
As this discussion indicates, there is an unresolved
tension in Benhabib’s account between democratic iteration
as a normatively laden empirical description of
processes of contestation and claims making around rights
and as a critical normative standard for evaluating those
processes and their outcomes. On the one hand, democratic
iterations are supposed to describe processes through
which universal or cosmopolitan moral norms are collectively
self-appropriated (legitimated) by communities
through democratic discourse and contestation. On the
other, the rigorous standard for assessing a community’s
process—for determining whether the democratic iterations
are genuine or legitimate—is precisely the norms
whose legitimacy for that community is supposedly established
through this iterative process itself (cf. 130).
Democratic iteration is a powerful and very promising
concept, and Benhabib’s discussions of real-world struggles
over the meaning of rights are often deeply insightful.
Yet I worry that in conflating the descriptive and the
critical in this way, her cosmopolitanism remains under
the spell of an illusion after all: that what is actually
happening in real disputes over rights is what discourse
ethics tells us ought to be happening in idealized discourses
about rights. Put differently, Benhabib’s cosmopolitanism
imagines that discourse ethics dissolves the tension
between foundationalist approaches to rights and political
ones; Karen Zivi labors under no such illusions in Making
Rights Claims. In this wonderful book, she argues—against
the pervasive foundationalist tendency in the literature—
that instead of worrying about what rights are and what
rights people have, scholars should focus on what rights do
(p. 9). That is, Zivi proposes to investigate and theorize the
process or activity of rights claiming itself in seeking to
grasp more firmly the normative and political significance
of rights. In this respect, her approach is similar to
Benhabib’s: She views the tension between rights and
democracy not as a problem to solve but, rather, as
a relationship to understand anew (p. 7).
In seeking to apprehend rights claiming as an activity,
what Zivi calls performativity, she “[draws] on the speech act
theory of J. L. Austin and the writings of some of his
contemporary interlocutors,” including Jacques Derrida,
Stanley Cavell, and Judith Butler (p. 14). The key insight
she takes from this conversation is that speaking, writing,
and other communications never merely reflect our world
but always also (re)produce it (p. 14). Performativity is
(necessarily) conventional, insofar as what we mean in
making an utterance is comprehensible only within a context
or framework of conventions in which it is performed.
Yet performativity can also be unconventional: What we
mean by making an utterance can call into question or
otherwise subvert existing conventions (pp. 16–19). These
unconventional performances, Zivi argues, are valuable for
democracy because they cannot be captured by any set of
rules, they open up rather than foreclose political possibilities
(p. 19). A performative understanding of rights claiming
undermines the familiar view of rights as trumps, a view
she finds pervasive and problematic.13 Seeing rights as
trumpsmeans treating themas if they create sure winners or
guarantee particular outcomes. This perspective inevitably
disappoints, as in fact rights often fail to deliver the hopedfor
results. Politics is contingent and conflictual, and
outcomes are never certain (pp. 36–42). Foundationalism
limits our understanding of what people do and mean by
claiming rights.
We can see this, Zivi argues, by recalling that political
activity often aims to be persuasive (pp. 46–47). On the
performative view, rights claiming becomes an intersubjective
practice of persuasion, and as such it relies on both
reason and emotion (pp. 118–19). As we engage with others
in politics and persuasion, she maintains, we share our
perspectives on the world, taking into consideration as we
do so the views and feelings of others in our community.
In the author’s gloss on John Stuart Mill, it is “through
this contestation and engagement with differences of
perspective that one comes to be fully human” (p. 59).
The meaning and power of rights derive from the
engagement and openness that rights claiming entail
rather than from any outcomes they deliver (p. 67);
this process is valuable for democracy not because of
the results it guarantees but because of the practice that
it engenders (p. 121).
This conceptualization of rights claiming also undermines
a familiar critique of rights focused on their
pernicious effects—their disciplinary power, their reproduction
of the status quo, their foreclosure of politics.
These critiques are less wrong than incomplete on Zivi’s
view; they miss the unpredictability and the transformative
potential of rights claiming. Invoking the discourse of
rights does replicate disciplinary power and reproduce
existing rules and conventions, but she also highlights
the unpredictability of rights and their transformative
potential. Despite their conventionality, rights can be used
to open up spaces, to introduce new perspectives, and to
challenge traditional norms (pp. 78–81). Rights claiming
is a kind of permanent provocation (p. 112).
In Chapters 4 and 5 of Making Rights Claims, Zivi
discuss
Most Recent Articles
“Might the Noble Savage have Joined the Earliest Cults of Rousseau?” in Jesko Reiling and Daniel Tröhler, eds., Entre hétérogénéité et imagination. Pratiques de la réception de Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Genève: Éditions Slatkine (in the series Travaux sur la Suisse des Lumières). 2013
“Politics Disembodied and Deterritorialized: The Internet as Human Rights Resource” in H. Dahms and L. Hazelrigg, eds., Theorizing Modern Society as a Dynamic Process (in the series Current Perspectives in Social Theory, vol. 30. Bingley, UK: Emerald (2012)
“Genetic Enhancement: A New Dialectic of Enlightenment?” in Perspektiven der Aufklaerung, eds. Hartmut Rosa, Daniel Fulda and Olaf Breidbach. Paderborn, Germany: Fink Verlag (2011)
“Individuals as Authors of Human Rights: Not only Addressees,” Theory and Society 39 (2010) 631-661
“Anti-Imperialism: Generating Universal Human Rights Out of Local Norms,” Ratio Juris 23 (2010) 289-310
“Deploying Cognitive Sociology to Advance Human Rights” Comparative Sociology 9 (2010) 279-307
Book 2012 ::: Human Rights as Social Construction
Human Rights as Social Construction
Cambridge University Press, 2012 (re-printed twice); paperback edition, 2013
http://www.upbo.org/catalogue/catalogue.asp?isbn=9781107015937
Guest Professorship 2014 Frankfurt/Oder
Philosophische Grundlagen der Menschenrechte bei Kant und Rawls
Patriotismus und die Linke in Amerika und Deutschland: Rorty und Habermas
http://www.kuwi.europa-uni.de/de/lehrstuhl/vs/politik2/lehre/Lehre-SS-14/Habermas_Rorty.html
Guest Professorship 2016 Innsbruck
Leopold-Franzens-Universität Innsbruck ▪ Sommermester 2016
Zur langfristigen Evolution
von Ungleichheit und der Konzentration von Wohlstand
LV SE 408.212 ▪ Modul “Markt, Staat, soziale Institutionen 2” ▪ 5 ECTS
Blockveranstaltung im Bachelorprogramm, in deutscher Sprache ▪ 12., 13., 19., 20. März,
Samstags jeweils 9-16 Uhr ▪ Sonntags jeweils 9-16 Uhr
Sa 12.03.2016 09.00-16.00 SR 6 Sowi
So 13.03.2016 09.00-16.00 SR 6 Sowi
Sa 19.03.2016 09.00-16.00 SR 6 Sowi
So 20.03.2016 09.00-16.00 SR 6 Sowi
Prof. Dr. Benjamin Gregg (bgregg@austin.utexas.edu)
KOMMENTAR ▪ Ziel der Veranstaltung ist es, Markt, Staat und Institutionen im Lichte der Gesellschaftstheorie von Thomas Piketty zu beleuchten. Dabei werden mehere Piketty-Kritiker aus diversen gesellschaftstheoretischen Richtungen mitthematisiert. Das Seminar behandelt Daten aus 20 Ländern, mit Rückgriffen bis ins 18. Jahrhundert, um die entscheidenden ökonomischen und sozialen Muster freizulegen, um die dynamischen Faktoren für die Akkumulation und Distribution von Kapital zu verstehen. Sind Gewinne aus Kapital höher als die Wachstumsraten, und somit der Haupttreiber der Ungleichheit heute? Inweifern ist der soziale Friede dadurch gefährdet? Inwiefern sind die Werte der Demokratie daduch unterminiert? Wie extrem sind die verschiedenen Formen von Ungleichheit heute? Droht die Ungleichheit von heute noch extremer Formen von Ungleichheit morgen hervorzubringen?
LITERATUR ▪ (a) Thomas Piketty, Le capital au XXIe siècle (französische Originalfassung oder die deutsche bzw. englische Übersetzung) ▪ (b) Mehere kritischen Stellungnahmen zu Piketty liegen als pdf-Dateien vor
HINWEIS ZUR VERANSTALTUNG ▪ Verpflichtend ist die Teilnahme an allen vier Seminartagen
LEISTUNGSNACHWEIS ▪ Für einen benoteten Schein: ein textanalytischer Aufsatz, der eine bestimmte Fragestellung kritisch und eingehend diskutiert, von 8 bis 10 Seiten in deutscher oder englischer Sprache. Die Themen zu den Aufsätzen müssen bis zum 20.04.2016 mit mir abgesprochen werden; eine kurze E-Mail mit einem Arbeitstitel sowie „thesis-statement“ (d.h. Abstract oder kurze Inhaltsangabe eines wissenschaftlichen Aufsatzes) reicht aus. Abgabetermin ist der 8. August 2016 per elektronische Zusendung (Email-Anhang in Word).
▪ SEMINARPLAN ▪
Pflichtlektüre ▪ Bitte vor dem jeweiligen Blocktermin lesen
Samstag, d. 12.03.16
09-13 Uhr: Seiten [deutsch] 39-48 [englisch 20-27]
und 785-793 [englisch 571-577]
und 313-342 [englisch 237-260]
14-16 Uhr: Seiten 342-381 [englisch 260-290]
Sonntag, d. 13.03.16
09-13 Uhr: Seiten 381-426 [englisch 290-321]
14-16 Uhr: Seiten 426-465 [englisch 321-350]
Samstag, d. 19.03.16
09-13 Uhr: Seiten 466-500 [englisch 350-376]
14-16 Uhr: Seiten 501-536 [englisch 377-404]
Sonntag, d. 20.03.16
09-13 Uhr: Seiten 537-571 [englisch 404-429]
14-16 Uhr: Seiten 573-624 [englisch 430-467]
Curriculum Vitae
Profile Pages
- Home
- Courses
- Book 2016 ::: The Human Rights State
- Yale Interdisciplinary Center for Bioethics 2016
- Seminar Planned in Shanghai and Hong Kong 2017
- Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, Oxford 2017-18
- Masterclass on New Book 2015 Glasgow
- Book 2018 ::: Human Nature as Cultural Design
- Ethical to Genetically Engineer Intelligence?
- Fulbright Professorship 2016 Austria
- Symposium on New Book 2016 Sweden
- International Seminar 2016 Japan
- Lecture, Raoul Wallenberg Institute, Sweden 2016
- University of Helsinki, Finland 2016
- Blog on Human Nature and Genetic Engineering 2016
- Review 1: Human Rights as Social Construction
- Review 2 : Human Rights as Social Construction
- Review 3: Human Rights as Social Construction
- Review 4: Human Rights as Social Construction
- Most Recent Articles
- Book 2012 ::: Human Rights as Social Construction
- Guest Professorship 2014 Frankfurt/Oder
- Guest Professorship 2016 Innsbruck